The 2024 Cuban Blackouts

On November 15, 1973, Fidel Castro made a speech to the Cuban Worker’s Congress. Reading over the transcript is very revealing of the fundamental philosophy and motivations of his regime in Cuba, which still exists to this day.

In the speech, he said that Cuba was not yet ready for the “communist principle” as Karl Marx had defined it.  What did Castro mean by this phrase?

This is an essential matter in the construction of socialism and our revolutionary and socialist workers understood that. In discussing that principle we have been discussing an essential and key principle of revolutionary ideology. That every one contribute according to his ability, that each one receive according to his work is a principle, an inexorable law in the construction of socialism. When we learn to understand this principle thoroughly we are penetrating the depths of political thought, we are penetrating the depths of revolutionary thought and we learn to distinguished it from another principle of the communist society established by Karl Marx: from each according to his ability, to each according to his needs.” (Speech by Fidel Castro, at the closing ceremony of the 13th Congress of the Central Organization of Cuban Workers on 15 November, 1973 (“Nov. 15, 1973 Castro Speech”), emphasis added, http://lanic.utexas.edu/project/castro/db/1973/19731116.html)

In essence, Castro distinguished “socialism” from “communism” by distinguishing it from Karl Marx’s statement that communism means: “From each according to his ability, to each according to his needs”:

In a higher phase of communist society, after the enslaving subordination of the individual to the division of labor, and therewith also the antithesis between mental and physical labor, has vanished; after labor has become not only a means of life but life’s prime want; after the productive forces have also increased with the all-around development of the individual, and all the springs of co-operative wealth flow more abundantly – only then can the narrow horizon of bourgeois right be crossed in its entirety and society inscribe on its banners: From each according to his ability, to each according to his needs!” (Karl Marx, “Critique of the Gotha Programme” https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1875/gotha/ch01.htm)

Castro said that the “principle of socialism”, as contrasted from this “principle of communism” is that “…every one contribute according to his ability, that each one receive according to his work…”(“Nov. 15, 1973 Castro Speech”), emphasis added.)

Why did Castro believe they couldn’t operate under the “principle of communism” in 1973 Cuba? Because the Cuban people were not “ready” for communism:

Many events demonstrate to us that we are not yet prepared to live in communism. Aside from the fact that in order to live in communism it is not only necessary to have a communist consciousness but to have abundant wealth spring from man’s work…” (Nov. 15, 1973 Castro Speech)

Castro says that the people are “ready” to live under “communism” in some areas, such as, supposedly, education and health care. But in other areas, they are not “ready”. An example of an area where the Cuban people were supposedly not “ready” was electrical production:

We can continue and ask how much fuel are we wasting? How much in the way of raw materials are we wasting? How much electricity are we excessively consuming? It is clear that with (?light patrols) and simple appeals to people’s consciences, we are not going to save on electricity. I raise this issue because the electricity problem is an unpleasant one which we will have to face. It is an unpopular problem, but we have to face it. [applause] We substantially reduced the rate of an electric company–I do not exactly recall which. The electrical octopus was using a rate which encouraged the use of electricity. The rate on the first kilowatts was higher and it dropped as you used more.

With our revolutionary inexperience we were improvident. We reduced the company’s rates by half and we were left with the same condition which encouraged more consumption. I say we were improvident because we should have thought of the day when the electric system would not be the property of an electrical octopus but the property of the people. Now the electrical octupus belongs to the people and the people have to pay for the consequences of any electrical waste.” (Nov. 15, 1973 Castro Speech)

In essence Castro said here that Cuba is consuming more electrical power than is produced because the rates charged to people are very low, or even zero. Basic economics teaches that when a price ceiling is set on a good or service, there will be shortages because demand outruns supply. (https://fee.org/resources/price-controls-and-shortages/) This is why you would see breadlines in the old Soviet Union, and grocery stores with empty shelves. The profit motive to produce more is eliminated, and no one is incentivized to produce more. In the case of electrical production, the result of charging insufficient rates for electricity, or giving it away for free, is that people will not economize, and there is no incentive to produce more, so there will be constant blackouts in the power grid.

Castro blamed the Cuban people for not being “ready” for communism:

“…a study of an endless number of facts clearly demonstrates that our society, our people do not have the culture necessary for communist life–aside from the fact that an economy sufficiently developed for communist life is lacking.” (Nov. 15, 1973 Castro Speech, emphasis added.)

In other words, communism, and the goals of communism are noble, but the Cuban people are just not quite “good enough” for it. Someday, the people of Cuba would be “ready” for Communism, so operating under the “socialist principle” was just going to be temporary:

It is a matter of making rectifications because we are socialists [applause] and because we want to be communists [applause–crowd chants Fidel, Fidel and rhythmically applauds for 30 seconds] and because we will never renounce the communist objective or our revolution and the development of our revolutionary consciousness…”(Nov. 15, 1973 Castro Speech, emphasis added.)

What is the “communist objective” it is, as Marx said: “From each according to his ability, to each according to his needs!” (Karl Marx, “Critique of the Gotha Programme”)

Why, according to Castro, is the “communist objective” desirable? Because Castro and his minions “…will continue, above all, to uphold altruism, selflessness and man’s solidary spirit.” (Nov. 15, 1973 Castro Speech, emphasis added.)

Castro went on in his 1973 speech to say, almost paraphrasing Geroge Orwell, that “All animals are equal, but some animals are more equal than others,” at least while it’s necessary to operate under the “socialist phase”, where everyone is not equal, rather than the “communist phase”, in some future paradise, when everyone will be equal.  In particular, Castro said it would be necessary for certain “administrators” to receive more for their, supposedly, “important work” than others:

This is another example of why we should develop a savings policy in all aspects, and especially with regard to fuel. It is here that the workers movement can give us extraordinary help. Wherever fuel is being wasted be it a farm, or a factory, or any place these are realities which our workers have to face. But a study of an endless number of facts clearly demonstrates that our society, our people do not have the culture necessary for communist life–aside from the fact that an economy sufficiently developed for communist life is lacking. Realistically, very realistically, we must implement the formulas which apply to this phase of our revolution, and implement in every aspect–not only in distribution, not only in wages, but also in administrationall the formulas which are applicable to the socialist phase of the revolution. [applause]” (Nov. 15, 1973 Castro Speech, emphasis added.)

In other words, the people involved in “administration”, that is Castro, and his gang of communist thugs in Cuba, would need to receive more money, bigger houses, nicer cars, and more political power, because what is more important than bringing about eventual communism? If everyone must “…contribute according to his ability…” and everyone must temporarily  “…receive according to his work…”, who, according to Castro and his cronies, was doing more valuable work than them? Aren’t they the ones (supposedly) trying to bring about eventual communism, which is everyone’s goal?

Castro’s 1973 speech is more than 50 years old. Surely progress has been made in moving the country towards “true” communism, hasn’t it? Has Cuba come closer to being “ready” to operate under the “communist principle” of from each according to his ability, to each according to his needs?

In October of 2024, Cuba experienced a days-long blackout throughout the country. I became aware of this by watching YouTubers in Cuba who were documenting their experiences during the blackout. (This seems to be not without risk. I assume these amateur videographers could be arrested and jailed for bringing the regime there into disrepute. I consider these YouTubers to be quite courageous.) What the blackout shows is that the Cuban people, in general, have probably gotten poorer, not wealthier.  The recent Cuban energy crisis suggests the answer to whether Cuba is more “ready” for communism than it was in 1973 is: No.

Of course, the Cuban regime, and its left-wing apologists have a retort to why Cuba is suffering from blackouts. They’ve had the same scapegoat for the past 50+ years: The United States and its supposed “blockade” on Cuba.

First of all, it’s not a “blockade”. The United States has imposed an embargo on Cuba. A “blockade” is when a country uses its navy to prevent entry or exit from a country, thereby preventing trade and the movement of people by military force. (https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/blockade) An “embargo” is where a country simply prohibits its citizens from trading with a particular country. (https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/embargo)  It does not use military force to prevent other countries from trading with the embargoed country.

The “US is imposing a blockade on Cuba” myth is so prevalent on social media that it was fact checked by a left-leaning organization, and found not to be true:

Cuba can trade with other countries of its choosing — if those countries are willing as well. Some of Cuba’s trading partners include China, Spain, the Netherlands, Canada, Mexico and Brazil, according to the Observatory of Economic Complexity. Venezuela was one of Cuba’s key trade partners until its ability diminished amid its own economic turmoil. Cuba’s main exports include rolled tobacco, raw sugar, nickel, liquor and zinc. Top imports include poultry meat, wheat, soybean meal, corn and concentrated milk.” (https://www.politifact.com/factchecks/2021/jul/19/facebook-posts/cuba-can-trade-other-countries-heres-some-context/)

The United States has simply chosen not to trade with Cuba. (Whether the United States, from the perspective of its own national interest, should impose embargoes is a debate for another time.) An important question to ask these leftist apologists for Cuba is: Why is Cuba’s survival so dependent on trading with the arch-Capitalist enemy, the United States? Shouldn’t socialism make it economically much stronger than the US? Cuba can trade with much of Europe, Latin America, Canada, and China. Can’t it get whatever it needs in trade from China, Iran, and Russia? If not, why not? What is it about these countries that makes them less productive than the United States?

But, the most important question of all is this:  If Cuba can have the material prosperity the United States enjoys, and end the embargo, just by adapting capitalism, why not just do that? Why’d they make the people of Cuba suffer under shortages and blackouts for the past 50+ years?

The regime in Cuba must believe either, or both, of these two things:

(1) Cuba will eventually have even more prosperity in the future by not giving in and adopting some sort of semi-free-market economy here and now, and/or;

(2) Adapting more free markets and individual freedom runs so contrary to their worldview, philosophy, and morality that it is simply unthinkable, even if it means many must suffer and die. In other words, the Cuban regime believes that the only proper system is “…from each according to his ability, to each according to his needs…”, and they will kill every last person in Cuba to achieve it.

The first explanation for why Cuba does not adopt free markets and a free society has pretty much been shown to be false with the fall of the Soviet Union in 1991. The Soviets waited 75 years, suffered terrible hardship, human rights abuses, and deaths, but the prosperity promised by Karl Marx never came. People living under communist regimes could wait 200 years, and prosperity would never arrive because it is a system that is contrary to human nature. It is contrary to what the individual needs to survive and function. Since ‘society’ is nothing but a number of individual human beings, any system that crushes the individual, ultimately disintegrates when it runs out of productive victims.

But, prosperity is not what really matters to the Communist. What matters is that everyone receive equal results for unequal effort. The second motive of the Cuban dictators, “…from each according to his ability, to each according to his needs…”, doesn’t require prosperity. It only requires forced redistribution of the production by the able to the unable. At the end of the day, Cuba is poor not because of any (imaginary) “blockade” or embargo, but because they follow a morality that destroys productiveness. At root, the Cuban regime is committed to a morality that crushes the individual spirit, and prohibits people from furthering their own lives and pursuing personal happiness.

The leadership of the Cuban regime are not looking for prosperity for the people of Cuba. They are only looking to achieve “pure communism”, a system that destroys the individual in favor of “selflessness”, and that will someday, somehow, “work”. Since socialism and communism will never “work”, in practice, it means the leadership of the Cuban regime will continue to cling to power -and use whatever repression of the people is necessary to maintain that power, forever. (Unless the Cuban people someday decide they have had enough, and put an end to it.)

How can Cuba achieve prosperity? Only by rejecting the idea of “…from each according to his ability, to each according to his needs…” In turn, this requires them to reject altruism, that is, they must reject the sacrifice of the individual’s life for some ‘greater good.’ They must recognize that ‘society’ is nothing but a number of individuals, and that each person has an inalienable right to pursue his own happiness. I’m not even saying they have to institute pure capitalism as described by Ayn Rand. (Not even the United States is that good, yet.) It just means they need to depose the current leaders of the Cuban regime, probably by force, and institute a freer government. A government that recognizes basic individual rights, with free and fair elections, rule of law, and, in economics, a generally free market, like the United States.

Only then will Cuba’s periodic blackouts end.

Conservatives On The Secular Basis of Sexual Propriety -A Trojan Horse For Dogmatism

I occasionally watch bits of a podcast called “whatever” on YouTube. It reminds me of “The Phil Donahue Show” from when I was a kid, although it’s more focused on sex and relationships. The host will have a panel of women on. Some of them will be involved in the pornography industry or doing sex work, sometimes including women that do legal sex-for-money work, such as in a brothel in Nevada. There will also be a person on the panel who represents the “conservative/religious viewpoint” on sex and romance.

Additionally, there will be some women on the panel who have more “average” lives, and are not sex workers and also are not conservative ideologues. The point of the podcast, from a “getting viewership” standpoint, is obviously to get the two “sides” into debates about what is and isn’t appropriate or acceptable when it comes to sex, romance, dating, and marriage. Often the debates will center around questions like: “How promiscuous is too promiscuous?” “Is sex before marriage okay or desirable?” “Is viewing or producing pornography okay?”

In the most recent episode I partially watched, there were two women who do or have done legal sex work at brothels in the state of Nevada, as well as a couple of women who do Only Fans pornography in varying degrees of undress.

The conservative/religious viewpoint was represented by Candace Owens, who is a conservative, Catholic podcaster. During the course of the podcast, she made arguments for why monogamy is preferable to promiscuity, and why things like paying money for sex, and polyamorous relationships are not desirable for the people engaged in such activities.

I saw Candace Owens making, basically, two types of arguments in the podcast, although she did not explicitly acknowledge the difference between these two categories of argument. They are the same two arguments that most religionists make about marriage, sex and romantic relationships:

(1) Non-monogamous relationships and sexual promiscuity are contrary to biology and fundamental aspects of human psychology. An example of this type of argument is the following, although I don’t know that it is explicitly made on the podcast: Too many sex partners before marriage make pair-bonding more difficult, and watching pornography will affect pair-bonding later. There is supposedly some scientific evidence for this, although that is disputed. (https://healthland.time.com/2011/02/09/do-men-really-bond-with-porn-spoiling-them-for-real-life-sex/)

(2) Non-monogamous relationships/sexual promiscuity are contrary to the Bible/Christian doctrine, at least as they interpret it.

The conservative/religious ideologues I see online make the first, secular, argument when they say things like: Women who are promiscuous when young will find it difficult to be in a committed relationship later. That may or may not be true -I don’t know. But, when pressed, the conservatives like Ms. Owens fall back on: Promiscuity is contrary to the Bible. In other words, argument number two. At the end of the day, conservatives believe such behavior is undesirable because it is contrary to their interpretation of the Bible. That is what really matters to the conservatives/religionists, not any sort of scientific or psychological argument.

There may or may not be evidence to prove the first argument, regarding biology/human nature. Even as an atheist, I still regard monogamy as ideal, and I try to avoid being too promiscuous. But, I am open to the possibility that I hold this attitude because of the somewhat Christian culture I grew up in, which might still be buried in my subconscious. For that reason, I tend not to pass judgment on people who choose unconventional sexual lifestyles, such as promiscuity, polyamory, or to be sex workers. (I think it’s easier to justify certain types of nude photos, sexual dancing, or erotic art as consistent with a healthy psychology, but again, I’m not 100% certain.)  All I am willing to say is that open relationships would not work for me.  (I would get too jealous to share a wife or girlfriend.)

I would like to see someone pose the following question to conservative/religious pundits making these two types of arguments regarding sex work and promiscuity: “If the scientific evidence will later show that promiscuous behavior before marriage does not affect pair-bonding, and it is possible to be in a long-term polyamorous relationship, or to be a sex worker without psychological damage, will you then change your opinion on this topic? Do you actually follow the science, or is this really about what you think the Bible says, evidence and logic be damned?”

This method of argument used by conservative/religious people extends beyond the realm of sexual propriety. For instance, they will use the same sorts of arguments when it comes to abortion. They will present psychological or medical arguments, which they allege are science-based, for why women who get abortions will be medically harmed by abortion, or that it will affect their psychology adversely. The science here may or may not be true, but, at the end of the day, they are really opposed to abortion because they believe it is contrary to their interpretation of the Bible. Even if there were scientific evidence that abortion causes no harm to a woman, or less harm than an unwanted pregnancy, the religionists aren’t going to suddenly change their mind. That’s because science has nothing to do with their viewpoint. It’s about religion, which is based in their faith.

Do the Conservatives/Religionists really believe that love and romance are important when they promote things like sex only after marriage? Religious institutions instruct their followers not to marry atheists because they would be “unequally yoked”, and they regard sex as a sin for purposes other than reproduction. So really, their desire for pair-bonding isn’t about love or romance, but about making yourself what they believe is a better servant of god.

More generally, conservatives will wrap up their religious arguments with secular-sounding justifications in other areas too. They will say things like: “We need religion to keep people moral.” But, why do we need morality at all? When asked this, they are probably going to say something like: “Morality is needed to keep people from committing murder and stealing.” If that is their reason for why they think morality is necessary, and if I can present a secular moral code and a secular basis for the criminal law, will they abandon religion? Of course not, because these arguments are just rationalizations. They want to advance their religion, and are pragmatic enough to use a secularist argument as a fig-leaf, if it suits their agenda.

Truly religious institutions recognize this, too. They will say things like: “Works do not get you into heaven.” In other words, not stealing and committing murder is not what they believe gets you into heaven, so they don’t really care if people are moral or not. The truly consistent ones realize that logic, reason, and science are irrelevant. Even “conventional morality”, such as “stealing is wrong” and “murder is bad”, is irrelevant to them. Many of these western religious institutions might not commit murder for god (yet), but they are certainly committing manslaughter.

Am I being hyperbolic? The Catholic Church forbids the use of contraception, even in the context of marriage. There is good evidence that the lack of contraception world-wide leads to unnecessary deaths for women. (https://publichealth.jhu.edu/2012/ahmed-contraception) The Catholic Church even opposes the use of contraception by married women with certain medical conditions that would make pregnancy unusually dangerous. They are expected to either abstain from sex or risk death if they become pregnant. I submit that this is advocacy of manslaughter by the Catholic Church. They are promoting the use of force by government to prevent women from using a device that will save their lives.

The Catholic Church will tell those women not to have sex. But, without sex, how do they maintain a romantic relationship with their husbands? The Catholic Church will respond that sex is an unnecessary aspect of marriage. I do not believe that assertion is at all reality oriented. More fundamentally, it also shows what the Catholic Church thinks of love. It is a belief in platonic love as an ideal. Sex is dirty and base for the Catholic Church. They view it as a necessary evil for reproduction, and nothing more.

Tying this back in to the ‘whatever’ podcast with Candace Owens, at points the sex workers claimed that sex and love are not connected. They said sex has nothing to do with love, so loveless sex without psychological consequence is possible. Interestingly, the Catholic Church also believes in love separated from sex. ‘True love’ between a man and woman is platonic, with sex as a necessary evil, for purposes of reproduction. This is what the truly dedicated religionists actually believe.

I don’t know if non-monogamous and polyamorous people can find lasting happiness with that sort of lifestyle. (I’m very skeptical.) All I can say for sure is it doesn’t work for me. But, swingers and sex workers are not the people who need to fear the declarations of religious institutions like the Catholic Church about how people should govern their sex lives. The people who need to be wary are the monogamous couples who want to sleep with their husband or wife without the psychological consequences of perpetual guilt and shame.

An Observation While Learning Spanish Via The Comprehensible Input Method

I have been trying the comprehensible input method espoused by this site to learn Spanish.

The comprehensible input method seems correct to me, although I admittedly haven’t studied the science that they claim backs up the efficacy of the method. It just “rings true” to me based on my own introspection and knowledge of epistemology and language. The method discards learning grammar in favor of using pictures, gestures, and acting while speaking to make it more like the experience of a child first learning to speak. It also completely discounts speaking a language to learn it. Your are supposed to just gather “comprehensible input”, as that is the only way you are going to truly learn, according to the theory. The input is “comprehensible” because you understand the meaning of the speech, thanks to the gestures and drawings of the speaker, even through you do not understand the language yet.
Something I’ve noticed when listening to native or near-native Spanish speakers is they will mix in certain English words that usually reflects some new technology or imported concept, rather than adopt a specific word for it. Although this can also vary. Spaniards call computers “ordinators”, while Mexicans tend to call them “computeradoras”.

In this video, I noted that the speaker, a Spaniard, called the act of snowboarding, “hacer snow” a few times. In Spanish the substance that falls from the sky would be called “nieve”, so, to his ear, the word “snow” is connected with the concept of snowboarding.

A Comparison and Contrast of Ayn Rand and Murray Rothbard On Warfare

Ayn Rand on Warfare

As far as I can tell, Ayn Rand did not write much about when a nation has a right to use organized physical force, on a mass-level, against other nations or other armed groups.

Her essay, “The Roots of War” discusses how Statism is the fundamental source of war in modern times. In that essay, she does not explicitly deal with when, and to what extent, a free or semi-free nation may use its military force. She does make it clear that a free nation should have a military, and that sometimes it should be used:

Needless to say, unilateral pacifism is merely an invitation to aggression. Just as an individual has the right of self-defense, so has a free country if attacked. But this does not give its government the right to draft men into military service-which is the most blatantly statist violation of a man’s right to his own life. There is no contradiction between the moral and the practical: a volunteer army is the most efficient army, as many military authorities have testified. A free country has never lacked volunteers when attacked by a foreign aggressor. But not many men would volunteer for such ventures as Korea or Vietnam. Without drafted armies, the foreign policies of statist or mixed economies would not be possible.” (“The Roots of War”, Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal, Ayn Rand, emphasis added.)

Determining when an individual can use force in self-defense can be quite difficult by itself. It becomes even more complicated when the issue is “scaled up” to a nation-wide or world-wide level.

Since I cannot find anything from Rand’s explicit writings on the conditions under which a country can use military force, I want to start by looking at her writing on when an individual can use physical force.

One passage that I have found helpful in making the distinction between the use of physical force in an improper way verses the use of physical force in a moral manner comes from her essay “The Objectivist Ethics”. In that essay, she discusses what is the difference between the use of physical force “in retaliation” and the use of physical force as an “initiation”:

The ethical principle involved is simple and clear-cut: it is the difference between murder and self-defense. A holdup man seeks to gain a value, wealth, by killing his victim; the victim does not grow richer by killing a holdup man. The principle is: no man may obtain any values from others by resorting to physical force.” (The Objectivist Ethics, Ayn Rand)

For Rand, whether force is “retaliatory”, which is moral, or an “initiation”, and therefore immoral, turns on her view of values, and who is entitled to those values. For Rand, a value is that which one acts to gain and or keep, with the ultimate value being “man’s life”:

The Objectivist ethics holds man’s life as the standard of value- and his own life as the ethical purpose of every individual man.” (The Objectivist Ethics, Ayn Rand)

So, one must hold “man’s life” as the standard, and the purpose of holding that standard for each individual man is his own life. Values are those things which one must have in order to live. Thanks to their rational faculty, human beings can create these values in much greater quantities than they would exist in nature. (For instance, agricultural technology creates much more food per acre of land than would typically be found growing in a similarly sized area of natural land.)

If each man holds his own life as his ethical purpose, then the values he creates, are for himself and for maintaining his own life. In the case of using physical force, whether that force takes the form of a punch, a bullet, or a bomb, it is an “initiation of physical force”, if one is attempting to obtain the values which others have created for their own sustenance. It is “retaliatory force” if one is merely attempting to keep what one has created for oneself.

Something that is not quite captured by the quote from Rand above is the case of someone not trying to gain the values of others, like a bank robber. Some people are simply trying to destroy the values of others, such as a terrorist who kills for some obscure political reason, or a “serial murderer”, who may kill not because they gain any particular value, in any rational sense, from it, but to satisfy some psychological craving. In that case, I think she would still consider this to be an initiation of physical force because they seek to deprive others of their values. So, I think you could expand the concept of an initiation of physical force to include both the use of physical force to gain the values of others, and also to destroy the values of others.

At any rate, Rand’s point is clear. It is not the physical act, the use of physical force, that makes something an “initiation of physical force” versus “retaliatory force”. The action itself may look the same, and the context in which it occurs will determine whether it is “initiation” or “retaliation”. For instance, you cannot merely see a man shoot another man and conclude with certainty that the man who fired the bullet has initiated physical force. You would need to know something about the conditions under which that occurred. For instance, if it was revealed that the person who was shot was wearing a vest of explosives under his jacket, and had just expressed an intention to go detonate it in a crowded movie theater, the shooter is quite probably acting in retaliation against an initiation of physical force. In that case, the man wearing the hidden explosive vest has taken affirmative steps to kill a large number of people by putting together the explosive vest, putting it on, walking towards the movie theater, and expressing an intent to use the bomb. He has initiated the use of physical force. (Although the act is not completed yet.) He has started the use of physical force, and that physical force is directed at the destruction of other people’s values, in this case, their very lives.

For Rand, a nation or a society is nothing but a number of individuals:

A nation, like any other group, is only a number of individuals and can have no rights other than the rights of its individual citizens.” (“Collectivized ‘Rights’” Ayn Rand, http://aynrandlexicon.com/ayn-rand-ideas/collectivized-rights.html )

Therefore, a nation and its military has no greater rights than the rights of its individual citizens. What would be an initiation of physical force for an individual would be an initiation for a nation. Similarly, retaliatory force for a nation is physical force that is not aimed at gaining the values of others or depriving others of their values, but at protecting the values of the nation’s citizens.

Murray Rothbard on Warfare

Murray Rothbard seems to hold similar views to those of Rand when it comes to the state as nothing but a collection of individuals.

Additionally, he would hold that all states, insofar as they hold the exclusive right to the use of retaliatory physical force in a given geographic area, are illegitimate, but I am not looking to address his advocacy of “anarcho-capitalism” here. I am instead considering his views on warfare, within the existing framework of nations, as he does in Chapter 25 of his book, The Ethics of Liberty.

For instance, early in Chapter 25 of his book, Rothbard says:

To be more concrete, if Jones finds that his property is being stolen by Smith, Jones has the right to repel him and try to catch him; but Jones has no right to repel him by bombing a building and murdering innocent people or to catch him by spraying machine gun fire into an innocent crowd. If he does this, he is as much (or more of) a criminal aggressor as Smith is.” (The Ethics of Liberty, Rothbard, Chapter 25, Pg 190)

But, what if Smith deliberately hides in a crowd of people, and fires his gun at Jones? Can Jones fire back? Whose fault is it if Jones accidentally hits a bystander during the course of returning fire on Smith, when Smith deliberately used other people as cover? Rothbard does not address the issue.

Rothbard then “scales up” his individual scenario to a group of individuals:

The same criteria hold if Smith and Jones each have men on his side, i.e. if ‘war’ breaks out between Smith and his henchmen and Jones and his bodyguards. If Smith and a group of henchmen aggress against Jones, and Jones and his bodyguards pursue the Smith gang to their lair, we may cheer Jones on in his endeavor; and we, and others in society interested in repelling aggression, may contribute financially or personally to Jones’s cause. But Jones and his men have no right, any more than does Smith, to aggress against anyone else in the course of their “just war”: to steal others’ property in order to finance their pursuit, to conscript others into their posse by use of violence, or to kill others in the course of their struggle to capture the Smith forces. If Jones and his men should do any of these things, they become criminals as fully as Smith, and they too become subject to whatever sanctions are meted out against criminality. In fact, if Smith’s crime was theft, and Jones should use conscription to catch him, or should kill innocent people in the pursuit, then Jones becomes more of a criminal than Smith, for such crimes against another person as enslavement and murder are surely far worse than theft.” (The Ethics of Liberty, Rothbard, Chapter 25, Pg 190)

Rothbard never seems to want to address, in Chapter 25 of “The Ethics of Liberty”, to what degree, if at all, you can risk the lives of innocent people in defending yourself. If you cannot risk the lives of others at all, then there are very few cases where even clear-cut acts of self-defense are justified. A bullet could always go astray and hit an innocent bystander.

For Rothbard, exactly who has violated rights, if you are forced to defend yourself, shoot an attacker, and, for instance, the bullet goes through your attacker and hits someone behind him? Common law legal systems would likely limit culpability to what is ‘foreseeable’, or some other similar concept. This is the idea that whether you commit a rights violation has something to do with your intent, and/or what you could have expected to be the reasonable probable result of your actions. So, if a bullet goes through your attacker, makes a weird series of ricochets, and hits someone you didn’t even know was behind your attacker, you are probably going to be excused from any sort of legal culpability. (It should go, almost without saying, that nothing I say here should be construed as legal advice.)

My point is, your intentions, your state of mind, to some extent, matters when you use force. Why does your state of mind matter? I think Ayn Rand would say it’s because it points to your purpose in using force. If your purpose in using force is to protect your values, that is different from using force to destroy another person’s values, or to gain another person’s values:

The ethical principle involved is simple and clear-cut: it is the difference between murder and self-defense. A holdup man seeks to gain a value, wealth, by killing his victim; the victim does not grow richer by killing a holdup man. The principle is: no man may obtain any values from others by resorting to physical force.” (The Objectivist Ethics, Ayn Rand, emphasis added.)

Accidentally shooting a bystander while defending yourself from a robber is not an attempt to obtain values. This is not to say that all such accidental shootings of bystanders should be completely excused by the legal system. Maybe some particularly reckless acts in self-defense should cause some level of criminal liability, but the level of culpability is probably not the same.

When you shoot a hold up man in self-defense, and accidentally shoot someone else, your level of culpability is lesser (although possibly not completely excused). Why? because you were not seeking ‘to gain a value’. You were seeking to protect a value. Your intentions when using force matter.

What does this all have to do with warfare? It gives us guidance on how to look at uses of force by certain countries. If a country is attempting to kill enemy soldiers and accidentally kills civilians in the process, this is not the same level of culpability as intentionally targeting civilians, because the country is not seeking to destroy values. Furthermore, it may even completely excuse the unintentional killing of civilians, in some circumstances.

Go back to the individual level for a moment. Imagine if a criminal shoots at you with a baby strapped to his chest. You have no ability to take cover, and you cannot safely run away without getting shot, so you shoot back and kill the baby in the process of shooting the robber. Have you violated the baby’s rights? I think the answer is very circumstantial, but I can see a set of circumstances where you would have no other choice. (It’s an extreme, ‘lifeboat scenario’, admittedly.) In that case, the fault lies with the person who strapped a baby to his chest and then tried to kill you, leaving you with no other choice but to die, or shoot back.

More fundamentally, how is the risk that you might hit an innocent bystander in an act of self-defense different from the possibility that, for instance, your car might suffer a mechanical breakdown while you’re driving it, go out of control, and hit a pedestrian? Both are actions aimed at enhancing or promoting your life. Both could have unintentional and even unforeseeable, deadly consequences for innocent third parties. I do not think that others have a right to be 100% risk-free from your actions. If that were the case, then things like airplanes would have to be illegal. It’s always possible an airplane will malfunction, fall from the sky, and kill a family in their home. Airline companies, to a certain extent, put us all at risk of death from crashing airplanes.

All other people have a right to is that you will not: (a) intentionally use force to deprive them of values, nor will you: (b) use force in such a way that it would be reasonably foreseeable that the force would deprive them of their values. (Examples of such unreasonable uses of force would be things such as: driving a car at 80 mph through a neighborhood street where children are about, target shooting with your gun in a field that children are playing in, etc.)

Expand the situation of the criminal using a baby strapped to his chest as a human shield to the national level. If an organization of terrorists hides behind civilians, and then fires rockets at your country, can your army shoot back with rockets? Again, it’s going to be very circumstantial. Sometimes, the army might be able to stop the attacks in some other way, such as an anti-missile system. But, sometimes, the army may have to fire missiles back, and, in the process, unintentionally kill civilians. In that case, the fault lies with the terrorists, not with the army. The terrorists are no different than the criminal who tries to murder you while using another person as a human shield. The responsibility for the death of any innocents lies with the terrorists. For Rand, I believe the initiation of physical force, the rights violation, lies with the person who used other people as cover while committing acts of violence.

Rothbard, on the other hand, does not seem to agree with this. For instance, he considers all nuclear weapons to be illegitimate:

“…a particularly libertarian reply is that while the bow and arrow, and even the rifle, can be pinpointed, if the will be there, against actual criminals, that modern nuclear weapons cannot. Here is a crucial difference in kind. Of course, the bow and arrow could be used for aggressive purposes, but it could also be pinpointed to use only against aggressors. Nuclear weapons, even ‘conventional’ aerial bombs, cannot be. These weapons are ipso facto engines of indiscriminate mass destruction. (The only exception would be the extremely rare case where a mass of people who were all criminals inhabited a vast geographical area.) We must, therefore, conclude that the use of nuclear or similar weapons, or the threat thereof, is a crime against humanity for which there can be no justification.” (The Ethics of Liberty, Rothbard, Chapter 25, Pg 190, emphasis added.)

First, it must be noted that this seems like a suicidal viewpoint. In a world where countries like China and Russia have nuclear weapons, to say nothing of North Korea and Iran, Rothbard’s apparent call for unilateral nuclear disarmament by freer Western nations would mean we’d be subject to nuclear annihilation at the whim of some dictator. But, more fundamentally, who has initiated physical force here? Is it the United States for threatening to obliterate North Korea should that totalitarian dictatorship attempt to harm our citizens, or is it the madmen (and women) in charge of that country? Does the United States gain a value in destroying North Korea’s ability to wage war against us, or does the United States merely preserve the values of its people -that is their lives, liberty and property?

(As an aside, I think Rothbard also forgets about a use of nuclear weapons that would not involve the death of innocent civilians. Imagine an island nation, in say, the East China Sea, that was being invaded by a much larger nation from the mainland. That invasion force would come in the form of a floating armada of ships. What if the island nation were to use nuclear weapons to obliterate the invasion force while it was still in the water? No civilians would be harmed, and the possession of nuclear weapons by that island nation would serve as a deterrent to invasion.)

Rothbard is also fairly explicit that all modern warfare is illegitimate:

All State wars, therefore, involve increased aggression against the State’s own taxpayers, and almost all State wars (all, in modern warfare) involve the maximum aggression (murder) against the innocent civilians ruled by the enemy State.” (The Ethics of Liberty, Rothbard, Chapter 25, Pg 193)

At root, I think the difference between Rothbard and Rand on the legitimacy of certain acts of warfare by freer nations comes down to Rothbard either misunderstanding, or explicitly rejecting, the fact that the distinction between an “initiation of physical force” and “retaliatory physical force” lies in what values are, and what ultimate purpose they serve. I think Rothbard desired to create a “libertarian” view of Rand’s non-initiation of physical force principle that is severed from Rand’s underlying view of values, and the standard of “man’s life”. I started reading Rothbard’s book, “The Ethics of Liberty” prior to October 7, 2023, but those events caused me to want to write something about his views on warfare in particular. In the future, I will turn back to a comparison and contrast of other features of his book to the ideas of Ayn Rand.

On The Nature of A Shoehorn

Sometimes when reading Ayn Rand, I will read something that seems true, but fairly trivial or unimportant to my particular life. This was generally true when it came to her description of the law of identity. I first read the entry in the Ayn Rand Lexicon on the law of identity sometime in the 1990’s:

To exist is to be something, as distinguished from the nothing of non-existence, it is to be an entity of a specific nature made of specific attributes. …A is A. A thing is itself.” (Ayn Rand, Atlas Shrugged, as found in “The Ayn Rand Lexicon”   http://aynrandlexicon.com/lexicon/identity.html)

I didn’t see why saying “A is A” had any importance whatsoever. Of course a thing is itself. So what? How is it useful to go around stating the obvious?

About thirty years later, I have at least some inkling of why this formulation is important. The following true story from my life will hopefully give some concrete evidence for the practical benefits of keeping the law of identity in mind in one’s daily life.

I have three shoehorns. One of which I keep in my car, mainly so that I can change into a pair of wingtips I like to wear when I go dancing. (I also typically keep the wingtips in my car.) The shoes are narrow, and difficult to put on without a shoehorn. (I have narrow heels.)

I try to keep the shoehorn in a specific place in my car, so that I always know where it is, and don’t misplace it. Unfortunately, earlier this summer, my car had to go into the auto repair shop for quite an extended time. I have another, older vehicle,  a Chevy Trailblazer, which I have been driving in the meantime. When my car went in the shop, I put my wingtips in the Trailblazer, along with the shoehorn.

The layout of the Trailblazer is different from my regular car, causing everything to be out of place, including my shoehorn. Back around early to mid-June, I could not find the shoehorn one day. I searched everywhere I could think to look in that old Trailblazer for the shoehorn, but I could not find it.

I finally gave up on my search and was starting to think I’d have to buy another shoehorn. I usually keep two in my regular vehicle, but the other one was still with that car, which was in the shop. I keep my third shoehorn in my home so that I can put my work shoes on. Since I was busy with other things, I never got around to buying another shoehorn. (I just made do with almost completely unlacing my shoes to be able to fit my feet into them, which is rather time consuming and inconvenient.) A couple of weeks later, I looked down in the front passenger side floorboard of the Trailblazer, and there was my shoehorn. I had searched that area, as well as under the passenger seat, even getting out a flashlight to illuminate dark areas. I had not seen the shoehorn, and yet there it was, lying in plain sight.

I joked to myself that this shoehorn was like the “ring of power” from “The Lord of the Rings”.

This reference may take some explanation for those who are not familiar with those books. In the Tolkien series, an evil magical ring that gives people invisibility and various other powers, is described as having a sort of “will of its own”:

Gandalf explains that a Ring of Power is self-serving and can ‘look after itself’: the One Ring in particular, can ‘slip off treacherously’ to return to its master Sauron, betraying its bearer when an opportunity arrives.” https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Rings_of_Power#Powers

In other words, the ring of power has its own agenda, and you will lose it, and someone else will find it when it so chooses. In the novels, Bilbo Baggins finds the ring after another character, Gollum, loses it. Basically, the ring decided it was time for Gollum to lose it, and for Bilbo to find it.

A few weeks later, I went on a vacation, and packed the same shoehorn in my suitcase. Guess what happened when I got back from my trip? I could not find the shoehorn again. I had only taken one suitcase, so if I had brought it back with me, the shoehorn had to be there. I gave the suitcase what I thought was a pretty thorough search, but I could not find it. Thinking again of the ring of power, I started to give up on my search for the shoehorn. Then I explicitly thought:

Of course, I’m just joking with myself. The shoehorn has a specific nature. It’s not magical, because everything is what it is, and nothing more.”

Explicitly thinking this way led me to the following additional thoughts: “What is the identity of the shoehorn?” I started naming its characteristics or attributes in my mind. I thought: “It’s small, and it’s dark. Both of which make it easily misplaced and easy not to see, given the nature of the human eye.”

I also thought: “What is the identity of my suitcase?” I then started thinking about its attributes. It has one main compartment, and it has two smaller, pouch-like compartments with zippers on the outside. I had checked all three of those locations, and the shoehorn wasn’t there. Then I remembered one other thing about the nature of my suitcase: It has a detachable, somewhat clear, zipper pouch about 10 inches by 5 inches in size. This pouch attaches on the inside main compartment of the suitcase, at the top, by a pair of snaps. I use it to hold toiletries, like my toothbrush. I also keep items in there that I always need, even when I’m not on a trip, like a toothbrush and toothpaste. In other words, there is always some stuff in this small plastic pouch that could obscure something like a shoehorn from my vision on a cursory inspection. I didn’t think I would have put the shoehorn in there because it isn’t a toiletry item. But, I decided I should check it out, and guess what I found?

I believe that this rather mundane example illustrates an important point. Sometimes you have to mentally summon the law of identity, expressly, in order to banish incorrect thinking. In my simple example here, I had “half-jokingly” thought the shoehorn had some magical or mystical properties that made it incapable of being located by me. As a result, I think I started to give up on my search for the shoehorn. It’s like that mystical thinking demotivated me to look for the shoehorn, because I was falling into a pattern of thinking that the shoehorn was somehow intrinsically incapable of being found.

It wasn’t until I willfully re-asserted a “mental framework” that was more rational, with the law of identity, that I was able to think clearly about where the shoehorn could be.

Just like everything else, the human mind has a specific identity, or nature. Part of that identity is that it can develop incorrect thinking patterns or habits, that are detached from reality. In this case, I was falling into the thinking habit of believing my shoehorn was somehow inherently without identity, and therefore unlocatable by me. By mentally summoning the law of identity in my mind, and rededicating my mental attitude to that principle, I was able to develop a specific methodology or plan for locating a lost item. Adhering to the law of identity led to my eventual success in finding the shoehorn.

I would add that adhering to the law of identity doesn’t guarantee success. Sometimes you can do everything right, and factors beyond your control make victory impossible. It might have been the case that I had somehow lost the shoehorn in my hotel room, and left it there. In that case, it would have been unrecoverable. But, by thinking of its specific nature, I was able to better exhaust the possible scenarios under which it was still in my possession in the sense of being lost in some other item of property of mine, like my suitcase. Adhering to the law of identity allowed me to banish any “mystical based” thinking, which thereby maximized my chance of success, even if that chance of success wasn’t 100%.

The law of identity is more than a mere tautology. It can be the difference between victory and defeat. (Or, between putting on my shoes and going barefoot.)

 

What Is The Right to Life?

There are two philosophical/political groups in contemporary society that I know of who seem to speak of a “right to life”, more than anyone. The first group are the so-called “conservatives” when they talk about the issue of abortion. They hold themselves out as being proponents of the “right to life”. The other group are those who admire or ascribe to the fundamentals of the philosophy of Ayn Rand, such as myself. How is the conservative position on the “right to life” different from Ayn Rand’s position on the right to life, specifically when it comes to the issue of abortion? What do conservatives mean when they speak of a “right to life”, and is that different from how Ayn Rand speaks of a right to life?

I will explore this issue below. My goal here is to contrast, not to refute, the conservative position with that of Ayn Rand. I am not primarily engaging in a polemical argument here for purposes of debate. This does not mean I am neutral on this topic. My position on this subject will probably be apparent. I have also expressed some of my views regarding this matter before.

Ayn Rand on the Right to Life

A ‘right’ is a moral principle defining and sanctioning a man’s freedom of action in a social context. There is only one fundamental right (all the others are its consequences or corollaries): a man’s right to his own life. Life is a process of self-sustaining and self-generated action; the right to life means the right to engage in self-sustaining and self-generated action—which means: the freedom to take all the actions required by the nature of a rational being for the support, the furtherance, the fulfillment and the enjoyment of his own life. (Such is the meaning of the right to life, liberty and the pursuit of happiness.)” (“Man’s Rights”, The Virtue of Selfishness, Ayn Rand) http://aynrandlexicon.com/lexicon/life,_right_to.html

Some essential features of the Randian view on the right to life include:

(1) Life is self-sustaining and self-generated action

In other words, individuals are required, by the nature of reality, to take action to produce the values necessary for their survival. The values needed to live, like food, clothing and shelter, do not generally exist in nature. They must be produced by someone.

(2) Rights are about freedom of action in a social context. What is meant by a “social context”?

Some dictionary definitions of “society” are:

“…companionship or association with one’s fellows : friendly or intimate intercourse…”

“…a voluntary association of individuals for common ends especially : an organized group working together or periodically meeting because of common interests, beliefs, or profession…”

https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/society

So, “society” is a group of individuals interacting with each other. For Rand, social interaction is about the gain derived from doing so, for each individual. Society is not an end in itself. “Society” has no existence apart from the individuals that comprise it. http://aynrandlexicon.com/lexicon/society.html

For Rand, “freedom of action in a social context” means the individual ability to act without certain types of force being used, either directly or through threats, to stop that action, by others in society.

What kinds action must individuals be free to take in a social context? They must be free to “…engage in self-sustaining and self-generated action…”

(3) Can some people have the right deprive others of their lives, in order to sustain their own existence?

Since each human being must be free to take the actions necessary to sustain his own life, and it is his right to do so, there can be no “welfare rights”. In other words, there can be no right for others to provide food, clothing, shelter, or the other necessities of life.

“The right to life means that a man has the right to support his life by his own work (on any economic level, as high as his ability will carry him); it does not mean that others must provide him with the necessities of life.”  (“Man’s Rights”, The Virtue of Selfishness, Ayn Rand, emphasis added.) http://aynrandlexicon.com/lexicon/life,_right_to.html

The “Conservative” Position on the “Right to Life”

There is a certain amount of difficulty in understanding and explaining the conservative position on this issue. There is no single “conservative voice” that speaks for everyone calling their self a conservative on this or any other issue. I will therefore highlight three different positions, taken by individuals or institutions, that I think will be widely regarded as representative. These are: Ronald Reagan, the Catholic Church, and Billy Graham.

(1) Ronald Reagan

Ronald Reagan spoke of the fetal “right to life” in a Presidential Proclamation in 1988:

One of those unalienable rights, as the Declaration of Independence affirms so eloquently, is the right to life. In the 15 years since the Supreme Court’s decision in Roe v. Wade, however, America’s unborn have been denied their right to life. Among the tragic and unspeakable results in the past decade and a half have been the loss of life of 22 million infants before birth; the pressure and anguish of countless women and girls who are driven to abortion; and a cheapening of our respect for the human person and the sanctity of human life.”  (Proclamation 5761 — National Sanctity of Human Life Day, 1988) https://www.reaganlibrary.gov/archives/speech/proclamation-5761-national-sanctity-human-life-day-1988

Reagan references the Declaration of Independence, which says:

“…all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness. That to secure these rights, Governments are instituted among Men, deriving their just powers from the consent of the governed…” (Declaration of Independence)

Rand’s position is similar to that of the Founding Fathers: “The only proper purpose of a government is to protect man’s rights, which means: to protect him from physical violence.” (Atlas Shrugged, Ayn Rand) http://aynrandlexicon.com/lexicon/government.html

Since Reagan believes that a fetus has the same “right to life” as a biologically distinct human being, he must have believed that government must take action to protect that right. (The contradiction will become apparent when we discuss what a “fetal right to life” would have to entail, below.)

(2) The Catholic Church

The Catholic church, and various Popes, have spoken on the issue of abortion many times. The Catholic church’s positions on issues like abortion is often very philosophical, and well thought-out. As such, their pronouncements are often very revealing of the institution’s fundamental philosophy and governing principles.

For instance, Pope John Paul II wrote the following on the subject of abortion:

Man is called to a fullness of life which far exceeds the dimensions of his earthly existence, because it consists in sharing the very life of God. The loftiness of this supernatural vocation reveals the greatness and the inestimable value of human life even in its temporal phase…. At the same time, it is precisely this supernatural calling which highlights the relative character of each individual’s earthly life. After all, life on earth is not an ‘ultimate’ but a ‘penultimate’ reality…” (IOANNES PAULUS PP. II, EVANGELIUM VITAE “To the Bishops Priests and Deacons Men and Women religious lay Faithful and all People of Good Will on the Value and Inviolability of Human Life”)  https://www.vatican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_jp-ii_enc_25031995_evangelium-vitae.html

Here, the Pope said that human life is not primarily its “temporal phase”, i.e., our actual biological existence, and the sum-total of our experiences, emotions, thoughts, goals, desires, and happiness. In fact, so says the Pope, our “life on earth” is not an “ultimate” but a “penultimate” reality. In other words, the life that you actually live is nothing but a mere means to the end of your “spiritual life” after you die. (Who determines what is best for that “spiritual life”? The Pope, of course.)

It is rare to see such an express contrast to Ayn Rand’s philosophy laid bare like this. Rand said:

Man must choose his actions, values and goals by the standard of that which is proper to man—in order to achieve, maintain, fulfill and enjoy that ultimate value, that end in itself, which is his own life.” (“The Objectivist Ethics”, The Virtue of Selfishness, Ayn Rand, emphasis added.) http://aynrandlexicon.com/lexicon/standard_of_value.html

By way of contrast, the Pope is saying that this life is “penultimate”, which means “…last but one in a series of things; second last…”. In other words, your actual life that you are living is merely a means to the end of your “spiritual life”, which is the “ultimate value” according to the Catholic church. The Pope says you are to sacrifice this life for a (non-existent) afterlife.

Pope John Paul II went on to say that the “threat” of abortion is the same as the threat of things like poverty, hunger, and disease:

Today this proclamation is especially pressing because of the extraordinary increase and gravity of threats to the life of individuals and peoples, especially where life is weak and defenceless. In addition to the ancient scourges of poverty, hunger, endemic diseases, violence and war, new threats are emerging on an alarmingly vast scale.” (IOANNES PAULUS PP. II, EVANGELIUM VITAE “To the Bishops Priests and Deacons Men and Women religious lay Faithful and all People of Good Will on the Value and Inviolability of Human Life”) https://www.vatican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_jp-ii_enc_25031995_evangelium-vitae.html

An earlier Pope said that the right to life comes not from the fetus’s parent’s but directly from God:

Besides, every human being, even the child in the womb, has the right to life directly from God and not from his parents, not from any society or human authority. Therefore, there is no man, no human authority, no science, no ‘indication’ at all—whether it be medical, eugenic, social, economic, or moral—that may offer or give a valid judicial title for a direct deliberate disposal of an innocent human life, that is, a disposal which aims at its destruction, whether as an end in itself or as a means to achieve the end, perhaps in no way at all illicit. Thus, for example, to save the life of the mother is a very noble act; but the direct killing of the child as a means to such an end is illicit.”  (Address to Midwives on the Nature of Their Profession Pope Pius XII – 1951) https://www.papalencyclicals.net/Pius12/P12midwives.htm

No “human authority” has the right to sanction abortion, which means the Pope has the right to impose his will over that of any democratically elected government. (So much for governments being instituted among Men.)

Given this authoritarian premise, it is no wonder that some Catholic Bishops are seeking to influence the American political system by denying communion to prominent pro-choice Democrats like Nancy Pelosi and Joe Biden. (https://www.miamiherald.com/news/article261652522.html )

(3) Billy Graham

Protestant Evangelicals tend to follow a similar line of reasoning as the Pope and the Catholic church:

Q: Where in the Bible does it say that abortion is wrong, even murder?  A: From the writings of the Rev. Billy Graham Abortion has divided our nation like no other issue in recent times. The Bible places the highest value on human life. It is sacred and of inestimable worth to God, who created it ‘in His own image.’ The Bible recognizes the unborn as being fully human…. We must never think that we can solve one moral crisis by condoning another, especially the crime of murder, for unrestrained abortion is nothing less than that…. The issue of abortion is not whether people have the right to terminate the life of a child; the real issue is whether or not people will insist on running their own lives according to worldly standards that oppose God’s law.https://billygraham.org/answer/where-in-the-bible-does-it-say-that-abortion-is-wrong-even-murder/

The only likely difference from the Catholics is that Protestants believe the information can all be obtained from the Bible. One doesn’t need an “intermediary” with god, like the Pope, to explain what God wants -you’re supposed to waste your life on nothing all by yourself.

Billy Graham believed that abortion was murder, and that the primary issue is not whether people have the right to an abortion, but whether or not people will insist on running their own lives according to “…worldly standards that oppose God’s law”.

Just as Pope John Paul II indicated, our lives, for Protestant Evangelicals, are not of ultimate importance. Our lives serve some “spiritual life” that we have after we die. We are to live not for our own sake, but for when we die. In practice, this means we are supposed to listen to people like the Pope and Billy Graham, and renounce our happiness in the here and now to the extent they say it is necessary to keep from “opposing God’s law”.

A Common Theme Amongst Conservative Voices On This Issue

All three of these conservative positions rely on the following assumption: The mere fact that a fetus is reflexively and biologically attached to the mother’s uterus, means that the mother has an obligation to allow the fetus to remain biologically attached to her uterus for nine months.  The conservative position on the right to life is not just that a fetus has a right to exist on its own, like an actual person, since it cannot. It has a right to be provided with nutrition, sustenance and biological protection from the elements while it develops.

It is undoubtable that even if the fetus could somehow be medically removed from the mother’s uterus surgically without damaging it, this would still be considered murder by the “conservative right to lifers”. (Since a very undeveloped fetus outside the uterus, say within the first few months of development, would die within seconds or minutes.)

To illustrate the conservative position with a more extreme example, if a woman told her doctor to surgically remove her uterus, along with the fetus inside, this would certainly be considered no different than an abortion by the conservative institutions and individuals listed above. They would consider it murder, even though the woman is in no way damaging the fetus itself. (She has simply withdrawn biological sustenance from the fetus.)

This is why the most consistent and philosophical of the three “groups” of conservatives above, the Catholic Church, see their view of the “right to life” as no different than the supposed “right” of poor people to receive free food, medical care, and other welfare benefits from the state:

“”Whatever is opposed to life itself, such as any type of murder, genocide, abortion, euthanasia, or wilful self-destruction, whatever violates the integrity of the human person, such as mutilation, torments inflicted on body or mind, attempts to coerce the will itself; whatever insults human dignity, such as subhuman living conditions, arbitrary imprisonment, deportation, slavery, prostitution, the selling of women and children; as well as disgraceful working conditions, where people are treated as mere instruments of gain rather than as free and responsible persons; all these things and others like them are infamies indeed.https://www.vatican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_jp-ii_enc_25031995_evangelium-vitae.html

Here, the Pope is saying that not only is abortion a sin, but so is free market capitalism. Employers and employees don’t set the terms of working conditions in accordance with their own self-interest. Furthermore, it is an “infamy” to let people live in “subhuman living conditions”, implying that the poor must be provided with housing even if they have chosen not to work to earn the money necessary to obtain shelter.

Later in the same article, the Pope makes his desire to redistribute wealth more explicit. The Catholic church is often criticized for causing hardship amongst poor Catholics by discouraging birth control. As a result, traditional Catholic families are often too large in the poorer countries of Latin America, resulting in real hardship, and even starvation, for those large families. The Pope’s solution to this problem? Don’t blame the Church’s birth control policies. Blame capitalism and the failure to redistribute wealth from wealthy countries to poor countries:

In the face of over- population in the poorer countries, instead of forms of global intervention at the international level-serious family and social policies, programmes of cultural development and of fair production and distribution of resources-anti-birth policies continue to be enacted.” https://www.vatican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_jp-ii_enc_25031995_evangelium-vitae.html

The Conservative “Right to Life” Position Is Really A “Right To Receive Welfare Benefits Provided By Others” Stance

Unlike the Randian position, which says each individual is free to take action to sustain his or her own life, the conservative position on the “right to life” is the “right” of a fetus to receive biological sustenance for nine months, just like the “workers” supposedly have a right to a “fair wage”, that is not set by free competition and freedom of contract in a free market. The fetus has the same “right to life” as is claimed by socialists when it comes to providing cradle to the grave welfare benefits to those who did not produce anything. It has the same internal contradiction, too. It ignores the question: Provided by whom?

If some men are entitled by right to the products of the work of others, it means that those others are deprived of rights and condemned to slave labor.” (“Man’s Rights” in Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal.) There can be no such thing as the right to enslave, i.e., the right to destroy rights.http://aynrandlexicon.com/lexicon/welfare_state.html

At least with the socialists’ “worker’s rights” we are referring to actual, biologically distinct, human beings. In the case of the “rights of the unborn”, we’re talking about enslaving women to imaginary people.

 

 

Whoopi Goldberg On Systematic Nazi Mass-Murder

I was rather surprised to see this controversy, since I think Whoopi Goldberg is correct:

“‘Let’s be truthful, the Holocaust isn’t about race, it’s not. It’s about man’s inhumanity to man, that’s what it’s about. These are two groups of white people,’ she said on The View on Monday.” https://www.theguardian.com/culture/2022/feb/02/whoopi-goldberg-suspended-from-the-view-after-saying-holocaust-isnt-about-race

Jews living in Germany at the time of World War II can’t really be called another race, in my opinion.

Mein Kampf asserts that they are another race. If you read it, you’ll see that Hitler saw the perceived racial difference as the reason for regarding Jews as a danger to the German people. But, I don’t see any evidence that would justify treating Jews as a different race.

I think the concept of “race” is most likely a real concept, that is based in reality. I’m not an expert, but it is my understanding that forensic anthropologists can determine a skeleton’s likely ancestry with high probability by examining their skull. https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/26270337/  (Although there is debate, about the accuracy of this type of determination. So my certainty on this issue is not 100%. https://www.science.org/content/article/forensic-anthropologists-can-try-identify-person-s-race-skull-should-they )

I think the outrage here derives from the modern notion that race is “socially constructed” or that it isn’t a real thing. In this view, the white majority is simply imposing something on black people that doesn’t exist for purposes of exploiting them.

I think a lot of that debate turns around how “race” is defined. I’d say I define it as something like: “Where most of your ancestors originate from in the last 10,000 years.” Biological populations can have a lot of variations, but biologists seem to have no problem identifying a plethora of sub-species within other animal groups besides human beings. For instance, there are 9 sub-species of Tiger, and they all look the same to me, as a non-biologist. https://www.livescience.com/29822-tiger-subspecies-images.html So, why is it controversial to recognize that people whose ancestors are mostly from Africa, Asia, or Europe are different sub-species? (Especially when its fairly easy for me to tell the difference just by looking at them, but I see no difference with Tiger sub-species.)

I will also acknowledge that I am not 100% certain on this issue. Much of what we consider “race” may, in fact, have no basis in biological reality. It’s largely a scientific issue to be decided by scientists, but I suspect the issue is not being honestly addressed due to the fear by scientists that they will loose funding or jobs if they come up with answers the political left doesn’t like.

The danger of Mein Kampf doesn’t lie primarily in Jew hatred, but in the fact that it advocates collectivism:

It took centuries and a brain-stopping chain of falsehoods to bring a whole people to the state of Hitler-worship. Modern German culture, including its Nazi climax, is the result of a complex development in the history of philosophy…

If we view the West’s philosophic development in terms of essentials, three fateful turning points stand out, three major philosophers who, above all others, are responsible for generating the disease of collectivism and transmitting it to the dictators of our century.

The three are: Plato—Kant—Hegel. (The antidote to them is: Aristotle.)” ( The Ominous Parallels: The End of Freedom in America, Peikoff, Leonard)

http://aynrandlexicon.com/lexicon/fascism-nazism.html

https://www.abebooks.com/servlet/SearchResults?kn=the%20ominous%20parallels%20by%20leonard%20peikoff&sts=t&cm_sp=SearchF-_-TopNavISS-_-Results&ds=20

So, at worst, Whoopi Goldberg is guilty of saying something that is likely true (Jews are a not a separate race), which is based in a premise (race is something biologically real), that deserves more study. It certainly doesn’t justify suspension from her TV show. (But, these are the times we live in.)

What Is Culture? Are Some Cultures Better Than Others?

The Dictionary Definition of “Culture”

An online dictionary defines culture as:

“…the customary beliefs, social forms, and material traits of a racial, religious, or social group

also : the characteristic features of everyday existence (such as diversions or a way of life) shared by people in a place or time…” (Definition of “Culture”, Merriam-Webster Online Dictionary, https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/culture )

A “belief” is an idea or set of ideas.

“Social forms” are presumably things like legal and political institutions, customs, and morals of a people.

“Material traits” would likely be things like the architecture, art, forms of entertainment, and methods of producing the material values necessary for survival.

“Way of life” I would assume to be something like: How people live, and what they consider to be important.

For instance, the “way of life” of medieval European people was church-centered, with a small hereditary elite, the nobility, in control of governmental institutions. This elite gave little provision for the dignity and importance of the individual lives of the rest of the population. The majority of the population lived at subsistence levels as farmers, tied to the land. (The serfs.)

This contrasts with modern, western nations, in which religious institutions are generally separated from the organs of state power. Governmental institutions are believed to derive their power from the bulk of the adult population, in theory, even if not always in practice. The majority of the population performs some sort of technology or industrial-based labor, rather than farming. Individuality is more valued. Individual freedom is considered important, even if most modern persons also believe it must occasionally be overridden to advance some alleged “collective” or “group interest”.

“Beliefs” and “ways of life” both imply a set of concepts and value-systems. At root, a particular group’s “culture” lies in the ideas and patterns of thinking they hold. These in turn affect their actions and behavior.

For instance, most medieval Europeans believed forgiveness of their sins could only be achieved through the church. Their actions would have reflected these beliefs with regular church-attendance, and confession to their local priest. When Pope Urban II urged faithful Christians to undertake an armed pilgrimage to Jerusalem in the First Crusade, the people listened. The set of ideas and patterns of thinking they held, influenced their actions. It’s doubtful today that the Pope could bring about a call to arms, even of the most devout Catholics. A declaration of war by a modern Pope would make people doubt his sanity, not fall out for military service. Politics are not considered the Church’s province in the minds of a modern Catholic, at least not to this degree.

Ayn Rand On Culture:

“A nation’s culture is the sum of the intellectual achievements of individual men, which their fellow-citizens have accepted in whole or in part, and which have influenced the nation’s way of life. Since a culture is a complex battleground of different ideas and influences, to speak of a “culture” is to speak only of the dominant ideas, always allowing for the existence of dissenters and exceptions.” (Philosophy: Who Needs It, “Don’t Let It Go”, Ayn Rand, http://aynrandlexicon.com/lexicon/culture.html )

Marxism on Culture:

Not everyone sees ideas or beliefs as an important causal element in what forms the basis of a “culture”. In fact, some thinkers have reversed cause and effect, making ideas and beliefs more of a product of particular social organizations.

Marx believes that ideas are nothing but a rationalization for the dominant class and one’s “material existence” (whether he is Proletarian or Bourgeois):

“Does it require deep intuition to comprehend that man’s ideas, views, and conception, in one word, man’s consciousness, changes with every change in the conditions of his material existence, in his social relations and in his social life?” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

“But don’t wrangle with us so long as you apply, to our intended abolition of bourgeois property, the standard of your bourgeois notions of freedom, culture, law, &c. Your very ideas are but the outgrowth of the conditions of your bourgeois production and bourgeois property, just as your jurisprudence is but the will of your class made into a law for all, a will whose essential character and direction are determined by the economical conditions of existence of your class.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto.)

Marx views the causation as reversed. Your “economical conditions of existence of your class” and your “method of production” determines your ideas, and therefore, your “culture”.

For Marx, it’s not just that someone is born to particular parents, then adopts the ideas of their parents and elders around them, by “mental default”. If that is all he means, then he could simply say: “A person’s culture tends to be the same as the ideas and attitudes of their parents and elders.” One’s “method of production” would have nothing to do with it. Plus, this would be an incomplete explanation, since cultures clearly do change over time. On this explanation, how have human beings gone from hunter-gatherers, to agriculturalists, to a modern industrial and technological civilization?

Furthermore, the phenomena of the change and evolution of the culture of particular groups of people has been noted by scholars. In his book, “Black Rednecks and White Liberals”, Thomas Sowell observes how the white portions of the American South were originally populated by Scots and Irish who brought with them ideas, attitudes and beliefs that lasted after those same cultural patterns had largely died out in Great Britain:

“…a common subculture that goes back for centuries, which has encompassed everything from ways of talking to attitudes toward education, violence, and sex -and which originated not in the South, but in those parts of the British Isles from which white Southerners came. That culture long ago died out where it originated in Britain, while surviving in the American South.” (Black Rednecks and White Liberals, Location 79 of 7391, Kindel Ed., Thomas Sowell)

Why do cultures sometimes change for the better?

Since a culture is nothing but human knowledge, the question becomes: “Why do human beings use their minds to gain knowledge, and prefer correct ideas to incorrect ideas?”

In the realm of material production, the answer is clear. Human beings learn new manufacturing techniques because it makes the production of the material values necessary for their survival easier, or it allows them to produce more values with the same level of effort.

Human beings learned how to make fire because it warmed them on cold nights, and allowed them to cook their food. They learned how to make the bow and arrow because they could take down bigger animals, and defend themselves from others, more effectively. Human beings learned how to make penicillin because it protected them from infections that would have otherwise killed them.

In the field of law, why did human beings go from the absolute rule of monarchs in medieval Europe to rule of law and republican forms of government? Because they found that their lives were less secure when a single man or a group of men had absolute power over their property, freedom, and lives. For those who wanted to live, a constitutional Republic, or constitutional Monarchy, better secured their lives.

Why do some cultures change for the worse?

This is a more difficult question to answer. Not all human beings want to live. For those who don’t want to live, no particular type of action is necessary. Fundamentally, those who value something other than living will have no need to conform their actions to the dictates of the laws of nature and reality. If you want to live, you need to grow or hunt for food, and perform a wide range of other actions. For those who don’t want to live, conforming to reality matters very little. Therefore, the truth or falsity of their ideas matter very little. A culture whose people care so little for life will regard building the Great Pyramid of Giza, and the enormous waste of resources and lives it resulted in, as fundamentally better than the buildings of modern-day New York City, which shelter more than 1.5 million people from the elements. Some societies are fundamentally opposed to life. Their architecture, art, and graveyards reflect it. Every culture is, fundamentally, a battle between those who want to live, and those who do not.

The “takeaways” from what has been said about culture so far are this:

(1) A culture is ultimately a product of human ideas, which can be right or wrong.

(2) What makes cultures right or wrong are the dictates of the laws of nature and reality, combined with the desire of most people to live their individual lives.

(3) When we speak of culture as the dominant ideas of a group of people, it must be kept in mind that within a particular culture, there will exist dissenters and exceptions. (This is one way how cultures can change and evolve over time.)

(4) Within a particular geographic area, different groups of people can have different cultures, even though they are under the same political system. This often has to do with their geographic origins in other parts of the world. (For instance, white Southerners in the United States, versus Northern whites, as identified by Thomas Sowell and others.)

Culture Around the World

One other aspect of culture, that hasn’t been expressly identified so far, should be obvious: Since different racial groups originate in different areas of the world with different cultures, when those racial groups come to another land, they will tend to have different cultures. (Even if one considers “race” to be an invalid concept, you can eliminate that term, and this fundamental truth still remains: “Different groups of people, originating from different areas of the world, with different cultures, will have different cultures when they come to another land.”)

When the dominant ideas of a group of people are less in accordance with reality, and make them less successful at living, what should be done? They should be persuaded to adopt better notions, and to change or modify their ideas and behaviors. This persuasion should occur both internally and externally from the culture. People outsides those cultures should do what they can to encourage change, and people from within that culture, who dissent from it, should do what they can to modify it.

Although individuals have rights to life, liberty, and property, cultures, which are merely ideas, have no right to be free from criticism, because of their mere existence. Furthermore, cultural groups that routinely violate individual rights to life liberty, or property can be stopped with an appropriate and proportional use of force from those outside the culture. For instance,  a group of people that practices cannibalism and ritual human sacrifice can rightly be dissuaded from continuing such practices, with force if necessary. The only limit to the use of retaliatory force in such circumstances is the rational self-interest of the people outside the culture. (There is no “white man’s burden”, which makes it a duty or obligation to stop the savage practices of less culturally developed people.)

Under no circumstances should people from a more advanced culture attempt to accommodate or give sanction to the ideas of a culture that are inferior to the ideas of the more advanced culture. Doing so would be tantamount to a declaration that ideas don’t have truth or falsity. Since the truth matters for those who want to live, it would be a capitulation by those who want to live to those who do not. The sanction of inferior ideas would destroy the more advanced culture, and lead to nothing but death and misery.

Sometimes a less advanced culture may have some ideas that are superior to those of the generally more advanced culture, in a certain context. For instance, the Norsemen colonizing Greenland in the 10th Century are theorized to have died out, in part, because they were unwilling to adapt to local geographic and biological conditions. They might have been better off adapting some of the hunting practices of the local aboriginal people. (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3309771/ ) But, this simply shows that no culture is immune from the dictates of reality, if living is their goal. If one moves to a different geographic location, he would have to take that new context into account. He will have to either come up with new technologies, or adapt some of the technologies of others.

Just like one cannot speak of “culture” without recognizing that there may be dissenters within that group of people, so too can one only speak of a culture as more or less “advanced” than another “on the whole”. Medieval Europeans, and certainly post-Renaissance Europeans, had a better conception of science and logic, giving them a greater capacity to adapt better ideas when they encountered them. Such an adaptability is, itself, a cultural trait. It is the concept of “objectivity”, applied to living. It is the willingness to recognize when one’s own particular ideas and patterns of thinking need change and modification to better achieve the goal of living. The European recognition of this fact is found in the high value placed on free speech amongst Europeans and European-descended people. They recognize that the free flow of ideas will allow for the adaption of those notions best suited for living.

Are there cultures in modern-day United States that need to be changed or modified?

Since different people in the United States have different ancestral origins and backgrounds, it is no surprise you can find different cultures within different groups of people here.

The ancestors of most black Americans today came primarily from Africa. (Leaving aside some amount of European DNA through interbreeding.) Since most people uncritically adapt the ideas of their parents and elders over time, the ideas of black Americans reflect this history in Africa and/or the history of their ancestors in the South as slaves.

The cultural differences between the average American with predominate European ancestry, and the average person of mostly African ancestry can be quantified to some extent.  What follows is the data I could find from Internet searches on cultural differences between blacks and whites in three areas: (1) Level of superstitious belief; (2) black belief in “conspiracy theories”, especially with respect to medical distrust, and (3) black parenting differences in the realm of corporal punishment of children.

American blacks tend to be more superstitious than white Americans:

73% of black US adults believe evil spirits can harm, versus 54% of all US adults. (Pg. 65)

78% of black US adults believe prayer can heal illness versus 65% of all US adults. (Pg. 65)

“The findings show that majorities of Black Americans believe in a God with a presence in earthly affairs.” (Pg. 54)

48% of Black Americans think God talks to them directly, versus 30% of all US adults. (Pg. 62)

(“Faith Among Black Americans”, Pew Research Center, https://www.pewforum.org/2021/02/16/faith-among-black-americans/pf_02-16-21_black-religion-00-8/)

Superstition reflects a less scientific worldview. It means a person does not have a firm grasp of concepts like the law of non-contradiction, and of the fact that reality operates in accordance with specific and predictable laws of nature. Superstitious people tend to assume that there is some unknown, and fundamentally unknowable, realm that affects their lives in ways that are essentially unpredictable. So, for instance, they will believe they can petition some supernatural entity in that supernatural place, and obtain benefits that would contradict the facts of reality. This is why someone would believe that prayer can causelessly heal an illness, or that evil spirits can harm them.

Superstitious people will believe that others have special access to a supernatural realm, and can use that access to cause them harm or good. They will tend to believe in things like witches and the “evil eye”. Belief in the “evil eye” is 29% amongst blacks and 36% within Hispanics. Only 11% of whites believe in it. (“Many Americans Mix Multiple Faiths” , https://www.pewforum.org/2009/12/09/many-americans-mix-multiple-faiths/)

Black Belief in Conspiracy Theories:

Improper methods of thinking will also tend to affect how one views success or failure in society. If a person does not see their particular set of ideas as having consequences for their lives, then when they see others who are more successful, they will not view their success as the product of better ideas. They will have a tendency to view it as some sort of “cheating” or manipulation of the system. They will see a more successful group as engaging in “theft” of what is “rightfully theirs”, often by some secret, behind-the-scenes, conspiratorial means. A penchant for what is commonly called “conspiracy theory thinking” will be the result:

“Several studies have reported a widespread belief in conspiracy theories among African Americans. Such theories have been shown to have possible deleterious effects, especially when they deal with HIV/AIDS.” ( Simmons, William & Parsons, Sharon. (2005). Beliefs in Conspiracy Theories Among African Americans: A Comparison of Elites and Masses. Social Science Quarterly. 86. 582-598. 10.1111/j.0038-4941.2005.00319.x. https://www.researchgate.net/publication/4747599_Beliefs_in_Conspiracy_Theories_Among_African_Americans_A_Comparison_of_Elites_and_Masses)

A belief that white doctors are conspiring to harm blacks causes differences in the health and life-spans of whites versus blacks:

“Despite advances regarding access to care and overall treatment, medical mistrust remains an important factor regarding clinical research participation as well as prevention/treatment-seeking behaviors among African American women.” ( Medical Mistrust, HIV-Related Conspiracy Beliefs, and The Need for Cognitive Closure among Urban-Residing African American for Cognitive Closure among Urban-Residing African American Women: An Exploratory Study Women: An Exploratory Study , Jennifer Rae Myers PhD , Howard University, Kelsey Ball PhD , Howard University , Sharlene L. Jeffers MA , Howard University; Journal of Health Disparities Research and Practice, Valume 11, Issue 4, Article 8, https://digitalscholarship.unlv.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1832&context=jhdrp )

Some will point to incidents like the Tuskegee Syphilis Study as an explanation for black mistrust of medicine. Using this one incident as the basis for throwing out all of medical science would represent an error in logic. It is the fallacy of hasty generalization. ( https://owl.purdue.edu/owl/general_writing/academic_writing/logic_in_argumentative_writing/fallacies.html ) If black people are not seeking the assistance of doctors because of this belief, then it is another cultural failing. They need to understand that the bad actions of some doctors, especially when they are government bureaucrats,  cannot be generalized to all of medical science. This hasty generalization is another example of how black methods of thinking need to be improved.

Furthermore, even if there had been dozens of such past incidents like the Tuskegee Syphilis Study, of particular doctors violating their Hippocratic oaths to perform unethical experiments on black people, this would not justify medical mistrust. Medical science, as such, does not discriminate against black people. It is a recognition of the laws of nature, applied to human health and well-being. There is nothing fundamental to medical science as such that makes it “anti-black” or “pro-white”, anymore than the laws of physics, mathematics, or biology favor a particular group of people. All such incidents indicate is a need for better laws when it comes to issues like consent to medical experimentation, and, more fundamentally, for the government to get out of science, and leave it to the private sector.

If black people believe a past incident like Tuskegee is reason not to seek medical treatment, then they are mistaken, and need to be convinced to abandon this bad cultural trait.

Black Parenting Differences:

In the realm of parenting, there are differences between American blacks and whites that also tend to result in bad outcomes for black children. Black parents are more likely to use corporal punishment on their children. 59% of blacks spank 0-9 year olds, versus 46% of whites. (“Corporal Punishment: Current Rates from a National Survey”, David Finkelhor, Heather Turner, Brittany Kaye Wormuth, Jennifer Vanderminden, Sherry Hamby,  Journal of Child and Family Studies,  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10826-019-01426-4 http://www.unh.edu/ccrc/pdf/CV358%20-%20Published%202019.pdf)

Corporal punishment is generally believed to be associated with psychological and developmental problems in children. (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/17874924/ )

What Is “To Blame” for The State of Black Culture? (It Doesn’t Change What Needs to Occur)

These three instances of cultural differences between blacks and whites leading to negative outcomes for blacks are just a small sampling. They indicate fundamental differences in methods of thinking between blacks and whites, and help to explain why American blacks are behind whites in terms of wealth and well-being. They point to areas of black culture that need to be changed or modified, if blacks are to have any chance of achieving the success of the average white American.

Leftists will tend to say white Americans are at fault for the cultural state of black Americans. They will cite slavery and “Jim Crow” laws. I disagree, but this debate is irrelevant to this discussion. The point is, regardless of who, or what, is to “blame”, black culture is inferior, and needs to be changed. A debate about why black Americans tend to be more superstitious, and to believe in conspiracy theories, is more about the causation and origin of these ideas. The left tends to say that these beliefs originate in the plantation system of the antebellum South. (I think they mostly originate in the black American’s African roots.) But, that historical debate has little to do with the fact that black Americans, to a larger extent, do hold these bad patterns of thinking and beliefs, and it makes them poorer as a result. It doesn’t change the fact that many American blacks need to check their premises, and adopt better ideas for living in the here and now.

[Note: If you found this blog post of value, please consider a gratuity. Give whatever amount you think the post was worth. (Please do not send me money if you know me off the Internet.) http://deancook.net/donate/]

The Ideas In The Communist Manifesto Compared And Contrasted With the Ideas of Ayn Rand

Over a hundred and fifty years later, the ideas of Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels live on, like a cancer that has metastasized throughout academia and intellectual thought. As an economic system political leaders espouse, Marxism may be dead, but the “Marxist mindset” continually pops up in new forms.

The latest incarnation of Marxism appears to be in the realm of race relations. Recently, the Governor of Florida, Ron DeSantis, presented a plan to teach school children “civics”. Essentially, as a conservative, Republican governor, he wants to teach children about what made America a great country. (Unfortunately, as a political conservative, with little understanding of philosophy or history, the Governor of Florida probably doesn’t fully grasp what made America great. I’m also wary of public schools teaching ideology, even when it is pro-American. But, at least his heart is in the right place.)

In the process of explaining about his civics courses, Governor DeSantis emphasized that there would be no funding in public schools for what is commonly called “critical race theory”. De Santis described this ideology as essentially Marxist:

“‘Critical Race Theory is basically teaching people to hate our country, hate each other. It’s divisive, and it’s basically an identity politics version of Marxism. It has no place in the classroom and certainly shouldn’t be funded by taxpayers,’ said the Governor.” (https://hannity.com/media-room/desantis-critical-race-theory-is-teaching-people-to-hate-our-country-and-hate-each-other/)

There is some debate as to whether and to what extent “critical race theory” is influenced by Marxism. (I believe it is.) But, before one could make the case for the intellectual connection between “critical race theory” and Marxism, one must first understand what Karl Marx said. That is the aim of this essay.

Here, I will be comparing and contrasting the ideas of Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, as expressed in “The Communist Manifesto”, with the ideas of Ayn Rand.

Marx’s Collectivist Method of Thinking In The Social Sciences

Marx, like almost every economist and social scientist before or since, starts with a collectivist vision of mankind. Individual human beings become interchangeable entities. He starts with concepts like “proletariat” and “bourgeoisie”, and never connects that to actual people, living their actual lives. Rand, by contrast starts from the perspective of the individual:

“Mankind is not an entity, not an organism, or a coral bush. The entity involved in production and trade is man. It is with the study of man—not of the loose aggregate known as a “community”—that any science of the humanities has to begin . . . .

A great deal may be learned about society by studying man; but this process cannot be reversed: nothing can be learned about man by studying society—by studying the inter-relationships of entities one has never identified or defined.” (Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal, “What is Capitalism”, Ayn Rand, http://aynrandlexicon.com/lexicon/individualism.html )

An example of Marx’s collectivist method of thinking can be seen when he discusses the “alienation” of the “proletarian”, whatever that is, from his labor brought on by industrialization. Here, Marx conflates a skilled artisan with a “workman”:

“Owing to the extensive use of machinery, and to the division of labour, the work of the proletarians has lost all individual character, and, consequently, all charm for the workman. He becomes an appendage of the machine, and it is only the most simple, most monotonous, and most easily acquired knack, that is required of him.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

Mechanization allows a low-intelligence person to do what would have required a skilled workman before, while the higher-intelligence skilled workman can focus on the design of the technologies and machines. Both parties benefit from this.

This always occurs with technology. The high intelligence and high ambition people develop ways for the lower intelligence and lower ambition people to do part of the work. Think of the difference between a command line operating system and a graphical user interface in a computer. Lower intelligence people, with less inclination to learn DOS or UNIX, can now use a Microsoft Windows machine. I think this example of Windows replacing DOS is an example of what Economists call “comparative advantage”. (https://www.econlib.org/library/Topics/Details/comparativeadvantage.html)

Imagine an Engineer and a high school dropout. There are two jobs that need to be done. The first job is the design of new computers. The second job is issuing commands to a computer to print out letters in an office, for the manager. Only the Engineer can do both of these things because the computer is quite complex, and it has no graphical user interface. It’s using some text-based operating system like DOS or UNIX. The Engineer has an absolute advantage over the high school dropout at both these jobs. In fact, the high school dropout can do neither job. Issuing commands in a text-based operating system is simply beyond his mental capability. The Engineer builds a graphical user interface for the high school dropout. Now, the dropout can issue the “print” command to the computer, by clicking on a visual icon to print out the boss’ letters. The Engineer prefers to let the dropout issue the commands to print the letter for the office boss, allowing him to focus on designing new and better computers.  By designing the graphical user interface, the Engineer has given the high school dropout a comparative advantage in printing letters for the boss as a sort of secretary or office worker.

In the Late Middle Ages, I suspect something similar happened with respect to skilled artisans. (This is more of a hypothesis on my part, that would require historical investigation to confirm.) The craftsman who made shoes, for instance, would both design them, and then also physically manufacture them. The assembly line system allows for splitting up of labor between those with high intelligence and knowledge and those with low intelligence or low knowledge.  The craftsman, who is good at coming up with designs for shoes, specializes in the design of shoes. He became what we would today call an “Engineer” -a designer of machines and products, but not the person who actually physically assembles them.  The manufacture of each shoe is broken down into simple steps that don’t require much intelligence or knowledge. (This process of designing the assembly line is usually done by another, Industrial, Engineer today. This is also an example of comparative advantage and the division of labor.) A single person need only learn how to shape a piece of rubber into the shape of a heel. Another person need only learn how to cut a piece of leather into a sole. Another person only need to learn how to make a shoelace. Etc., etc. These simple steps can be performed by people with relatively low intelligence, and/or who have little education. The Engineer created jobs for low-skilled/low-intelligence people that didn’t exist before, which allows the Engineer to focus on more creative endeavors.

Marx fails to see the phenomena of comparative advantage probably because of his collectivist mindset. He thinks of “workers” as interchangeable. To Marx, the Medieval craftsman is the same person that would then be put on an assembly line doing “mind-numbing” manual labor. In reality, that craftsman is the high-intelligence, high-knowledge person who is more likely to become the Engineer, who has created jobs for many low-intelligence and low-knowledge farm-hands or vagabonds. The Engineer has an absolute advantage over the factory worker – he could do both jobs better. Due to the principle of comparative advantage, however, which is based in the Engineer’s opportunity costs, he prefers to specialize in the design of products like shoes, while letting others physically assemble them.

I think this is what Ayn Rand meant when she spoke of the “pyramid of ability”:

“When you live in a rational society, where men are free to trade, you receive an incalculable bonus: the material value of your work is determined not only by your effort, but by the effort of the best productive minds who exist in the world around you.

When you work in a modern factory, you are paid, not only for your labor, but for all the productive genius which has made that factory possible: for the work of the industrialist who built it, for the work of the investor who saved the money to risk on the untried and the new, for the work of the engineer who designed the machines of which you are pushing the levers, for the work of the inventor who created the product which you spend your time on making, for the work of the scientist who discovered the laws that went into the making of that product, for the work of the philosopher who taught men how to think and whom you spend your time denouncing.

The machine, the frozen form of a living intelligence, is the power that expands the potential of your life by raising the productivity of your time. If you worked as a blacksmith in the mystics’ Middle Ages, the whole of your earning capacity would consist of an iron bar produced by your hands in days and days of effort. How many tons of rail do you produce per day if you work for Hank Rearden [an industrialist and inventor]? Would you dare to claim that the size of your pay check was created solely by your physical labor and that those rails were the product of your muscles? The standard of living of that blacksmith is all that your muscles are worth; the rest is a gift from Hank Rearden.” (Ayn Rand, Atlas Shrugged.)

In the above quoted passage from “The Communist Manifesto”, Marx wants to make it seem like the skilled workman has been “alienated” from his labor -whatever that means. But, the skilled workman of the Middle Ages is the Engineer of today. The Engineer, backed up by the intellect of scientists like Isaac Newton, who were in turn backed up by the intellect of philosophers like Aristotle, created wealth for countless starving Medieval serfs and peasants, living a precarious, near-starvation, and very unfree, existence until the Industrial Revolution. The Engineer presumably gains enormous satisfaction from the design of new products and advancing the boundaries of technology and civilization. He’s hardly “alienated” from his labor. (Whatever “alienated” means in this context.) He derives a sense of purpose and meaning from his work. The assembly line worker making shoe heels, or the office worker using Microsoft Windows, can earn sufficient wealth more quickly, thanks to new technology. This gives some of these workers time to improve their skills by going to school if they are young, intelligent, and ambitious. If an assembly line or office worker is older, and perhaps of lower intelligence, it allows him to earn his daily bread more quickly. Then, he can get home to his wife and children. He may find his meaning and purpose in life through his growing family, rather than through his job. Either way, the assembly line worker and the office worker are better able to find whatever meaning there is to be found in their individual lives, thanks to the likes of Aristotle, Newton, and Thomas Edison.

Given Marx’s Collectivist Method of Thinking About Society, He Develops Poorly-Defined Terms Like “Proletariat” and “Bourgeois”

The Communist Manifesto is based in the assumption of a “class struggle”:

“The history of all hitherto existing society is the history of class struggles.

Freeman and slave, patrician and plebeian, lord and serf, guild-master(3) and journeyman, in a word, oppressor and oppressed, stood in constant opposition to one another, carried on an uninterrupted, now hidden, now open fight, a fight that each time ended, either in a revolutionary reconstitution of society at large, or in the common ruin of the contending classes.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

Marx says that “in a word” society that has existed until now has always been one of “class struggles” between “oppressor” and “oppressed”.

Marx and Engels speak of “oppressor and oppressed”, which forms the basis of the “class struggle”, which in turn is the history of all “hitherto existing society”, but what does it mean, “to oppress”?

Ayn Rand doesn’t speak of “oppression”, per se, but of concepts of “justice” and “individual rights”. For Rand, rights are violated by means of the initiation of physical force:

“Man’s rights can be violated only by the use of physical force. It is only by means of physical force that one man can deprive another of his life, or enslave him, or rob him, or prevent him from pursuing his own goals, or compel him to act against his own rational judgment.” (The Virtue of Selfishness, “The Nature of Government”, Ayn Rand.)

“Oppression” implies the use of physical force in an unjust manner, or at least action in an unjust manner. What is Marx/Engels’ theory of justice? What does the term “justice” mean to them?  As will be discussed later, the logical implication of Marxism is that “justice” is nothing but a “tool” of the ruling class, and has no objective connection to the facts of reality or man’s life. The concept of “objectivity”, of true and false, would be considered a “bourgeoisie prejudice” by anyone following Marx and Engels’ ideas to their logical conclusion.

The Communist Manifesto assumes an inherent and inevitable conflict between different groups of people. Class relations are always class conflict. Force is the only means of conflict resolution. One side or the other will be destroyed:

“…the collisions between individual workmen and individual bourgeois take more and more the character of collisions between two classes.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

“Here and there, the contest breaks out into riots.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

“…every class struggle is a political struggle.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

“In depicting the most general phases of the development of the proletariat, we traced the more or less veiled civil war, raging within existing society, up to the point where that war breaks out into open revolution, and where the violent overthrow of the bourgeoisie lays the foundation for the sway of the proletariat.”  (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

Rand, by contrast, says that there are no conflicts of interest amongst rational men, in the ordinary course of life. (Possibly leaving aside “lifeboat emergencies”):

“The Objectivist ethics holds that human good does not require human sacrifices and cannot be achieved by the sacrifice of anyone to anyone. It holds that the rational interests of men do not clash—that there is no conflict of interests among men who do not desire the unearned, who do not make sacrifices nor accept them, who deal with one another as traders, giving value for value.” (The Virtue of Selfishness, “The Objectivist Ethics”, Ayn Rand)

Instead of poorly defined terms like “proletariat” and “bourgeoisie”, Rand describes the “producer” and the “looter” as two groups of people fundamentally at odds:

“With very rare and brief exceptions, pre-capitalist societies had no place for the creative power of man’s mind, neither in the creation of ideas nor in the creation of wealth. Reason and its practical expression -free trade- were forbidden as a sin and a crime, or were tolerated, usually as ignoble activities, under the control of authorities who could revoke the tolerance at whim. Such societies were ruled by faith and its practical expression: force. There were no makers of knowledge and no makers of wealth; there were only witch doctors and tribal chiefs. These two figures dominate every anti-rational period of history, whether one calls them tribal chief and witch doctor -or absolute monarch and religious leader…” (For The New Intellectual, Ayn Rand.)

“You stand in the midst of the greatest achievement of the greatest productive civilization [The United States of America] and you wonder why it’s crumbling around you, while you’re damning its life-blood -money….Throughout men’s history, money was always seized by looters of one brand or another, whose names changed, but whose method remained the same: to seize wealth by force and to keep the producers bound, demeaned, defamed, deprived of honor. That phrase about the evil of money, which you mouth with such righteous recklessness, comes from a time when wealth was produced by the labor of slaves -slaves who repeated the motions once discovered by somebody’s mind and left unimproved for centuries. So long as production was ruled by force, and wealth was obtained by conquest, there was little to conquer. Yet through all the centuries of stagnation and starvation, men exalted the looters, as aristocrats of the sword, as aristocrats of birth, as aristocrats of the bureau, and despised the producers, as slaves, as traders, as shopkeepers -as industrialists.” (Atlas Shrugged, Ayn Rand)

Marx failed to distinguish between those who achieve wealth through production, and those who seize it by means of the initiation of physical force. To him, the Medieval nobility that held people in virtual slavery as serfs, and by force of arms, was no different from the voluntary relationship between the owner of a factory and one of his employees. But, one uses whips and weapons, while the other uses dollars and persuasion.

Marx on the Origin of the “Bourgeoise” and “Proletariat”

Although it is not a well-defined term, Marx describes the “bourgeoise” as having started out as medieval serfs, who formed independent towns in the European Middle Ages, then eventually displaced the Nobility and Monarchy altogether, to form the “modern state”:

“From the serfs of the Middle Ages sprang the chartered burghers of the earliest towns. From these burgesses the first elements of the bourgeoisie were developed. “(Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

“Each step in the development of the bourgeoisie was accompanied by a corresponding political advance of that class. An oppressed class under the sway of the feudal nobility…or the absolute monarchy as a counterpoise against the nobility…in the modern representative State, exclusive political sway. The executive of the modern state is but a committee for managing the common affairs of the whole bourgeoisie.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

This is a fairly accurate description of how medieval towns formed. Historians have described the rise of the “burgers” and the “bourgeois”, who were often escaped serfs that had run away from the manor they were legally tied to:

“The term bourgeois originated in medieval France, where it denoted an inhabitant of a walled town.” ( https://www.britannica.com/topic/bourgeoisie )

These towns did form the social and economic basis on which Europe moved from its medieval social and economic organization to modern society:

“While the manor remained the principal unit of European society until the eighteenth century, the seeds of ‘modern’ civilization were being nourished as early as the eleventh. With the reopening of trade routes and the appearance of new marketing centers came the emergence of the towns that were destined to convert Europe from a rural to an urban society. The lords and peasants who remained on the manorial estates played a negligible role in the growth of these towns. An expanded cast of characters gradually appeared there, consisting of merchants, entrpeneurs, bankers, lawyers, artisans, and unskilled laborers. In the thirteenth century these groups made up but a fraction of Europe’s population (less than 10 percent), but their numbers were destined to grow until, by the twentieth century, they would be a majority….

…The mideval towns were essentially trading posts where local produce could be sold and foreign merchandise purchased…

The new towns presented an avenue of escape to men and women who were seeking release from the drudgery and routine of the manorial village. This was especially true for serfs who longed to cast off their inferior status. They could, if they grew desparate enough, run away from the manor and lose themselves in a distant town. According to custom of the period, they were legally free if the lord failed to recapture them within a ‘year and a day.’ (Later in the Middle Ages serfs could gain their freedom by making a cash payment to their lord.)” (A Brief History of Western Man, 3d Ed., Chapter 5, The Creation of Europe: Political and Social Foundations, by Thomas H. Greer)

Marx/Engels show ambivalence on whether the bourgeoise destruction of the old medieval order was a positive change. In fact, they seem to regard many aspects of pre-modern times as superior to the present, capitalist order:

“The bourgeoisie, wherever it has got the upper hand, has put an end to all feudal, patriarchal, idyllic relations. … It has resolved personal worth into exchange value, and in place of the numberless indefeasible chartered freedoms, has set up that single, unconscionable freedom – Free Trade. In one word, for exploitation, veiled by religious and political illusions, it has substituted naked, shameless, direct, brutal exploitation….

The bourgeoisie has torn away from the family its sentimental veil, and has reduced the family relation to a mere money relation….

The bourgeoisie has disclosed how it came to pass that the brutal display of vigour in the Middle Ages, which reactionaries so much admire, found its fitting complement in the most slothful indolence.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto; emphasis added.)

These above passages seem strange in light of Marx/Engels’ belief that all of history is the history of oppressor and oppressed. It also seems odd because of their belief that the bourgeoisie had their origins in runaway serfs who went to the towns and formed armed associations for mutual protection.

Marx/Engels, at least implicitly, seem to prefer the social organization of the Middle Ages to social relations existing since the Industrial Revolution and Capitalism.

Other Randian intellectuals have noted that socialists are often “closet medievalists”. While he was still associated with Ayn Rand’s philosophy, Nathaniel Brandon made this observation about psychologist Erich Fromm:

Scratch a collectivist and you will usually find a medievalist. Fromm is not an exception. Like so many socialists, he is a glamorizer of the Middle Ages. He [Erich Fromm] perfunctorily acknowledges the faults of that historical period—but in contrasting it with the capitalism that succeeded it, he is enchanted by what he regards as its virtues….

… It is not uncommon to encounter this sort of perspective on the Middle Ages, among writers on alienation…. The complete lack of control over any aspect of one’s existence, the ruthless suppression of intellectual freedom, the paralyzing restrictions on any form of individual initiative and independence—these are cardinal characteristics of the Middle Ages…. all of this is swept aside, so entranced is Fromm by the vision of a world in which men did not have to invent and compete, they had only to submit and obey.” (Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal, “Alienation”, Nathaniel Brandon, emphasis added.)

Additionally, Marx/Engels certainly prefer the tribal pre-historical past of mankind, which they regard as a sort of “lost golden age” of communism. The Communist Manifesto hints at a distant past in which there was no class struggle:

“That is, all written history. In 1847, the pre-history of society, the social organisation existing previous to recorded history, all but unknown. Since then, August von Haxthausen (1792–1866) discovered common ownership of land in Russia, Georg Ludwig von Maurer proved it to be the social foundation from which all Teutonic races started in history, and, by and by, village communities were found to be, or to have been, the primitive form of society everywhere from India to Ireland. The inner organisation of this primitive communistic society was laid bare, in its typical form, by Lewis Henry Morgan’s (1818–1861) crowning discovery of the true nature of the gens and its relation to the tribe. With the dissolution of the primeval communities, society begins to be differentiated into separate and finally antagonistic classes. I have attempted to retrace this dissolution in The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and the State, second edition, Stuttgart, 1886. [Engels, 1888 English Edition and 1890 German Edition (with the last sentence omitted)] “ (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

“The “Manifesto” being our joint production, I consider myself bound to state that the fundamental proposition which forms its nucleus, belongs to Marx. That proposition is: that in every historical epoch, the prevailing mode of economic production and exchange, and the social organization necessarily following from it, form the basis upon which is built up, and from which alone can be explained, the political and intellectual history of that epoch; that consequently the whole history of mankind (since the dissolution of primitive tribal society, holding land in common ownership) has been a history of class struggles, contests between exploiting and exploited, ruling and oppressed classes” (Engles, Preface to Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

This is significant today, given the “multicultural” turn of modern leftism, in which primitive, “indigenous societies”, are viewed as “pure” and “good” while Modern, Western Civilization is viewed as always bad. There is textual support in The Communist Manifesto for this viewpoint held by the modern left.

Rand agrees that primitive tribes were fundamentally collectivist in organization. Unlike Marx and Engels, she recognizes that the modern move away from primitive tribes promotes and enhances the life of any person who wants to flourish. The “morality of altruism”, for Rand, is a “tribal phenomenon”:

“It is obvious why the morality of altruism is a tribal phenomenon. Prehistorical men were physically unable to survive without clinging to a tribe for leadership and protection against other tribes. The cause of altruism’s perpetuation into civilized eras is not physical, but psycho-epistemological: the men of self-arrested, perceptual mentality are unable to survive without tribal leadership and “protection” against reality. The doctrine of self-sacrifice does not offend them: they have no sense of self or of personal value—they do not know what it is that they are asked to sacrifice—they have no firsthand inkling of such things as intellectual integrity, love of truth, personally chosen values, or a passionate dedication to an idea.” (Philosophy: Who Needs It, “Selfishness Without A Self”, Ayn Rand.)

The Communist Manifesto seems to say the “proletariat” was inadvertently created by the “bourgeoisie”:

“But not only has the bourgeoisie forged the weapons that bring death to itself; it has also called into existence the men who are to wield those weapons – the modern working class – the proletarians. “ (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

What is this “proletariat”?

“In proportion as the bourgeoisie, i.e., capital, is developed, in the same proportion is the proletariat, the modern working class, developed – a class of labourers, who live only so long as they find work, and who find work only so long as their labour increases capital. These labourers, who must sell themselves piecemeal, are a commodity, like every other article of commerce, and are consequently exposed to all the vicissitudes of competition, to all the fluctuations of the market. “ (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

As already discussed, Marx’s description of those who own no property and live solely by being paid a wage is simply not an accurate description of reality under capitalism. Marx and Engels apparently had no concept of the economic concept of comparative advantage. They also had not even the slightest inkling of the “pyramid of ability” Ayn Rand has described. Capitalism and technological progress often create new jobs for people who have low skills or low intelligence. The example of the movement from text-based operating systems to graphical user interfaces, already discussed, is an example of this. Software engineers and entrepreneurs have made it possible for people with minimal computer skills to operate a computer by clicking on a series of “icons” on a computer screen. (Which was another invention -at one time all input and output on a computer was nothing but punched cards, requiring highly specialized knowledge and great intelligence to understand.) Every person working for wages in an office today has capitalism, and the technological inventiveness it unlocks, to thank for their increased productivity, which makes their higher standard of living possible:

“In proportion to the mental energy he spent, the man who creates a new invention receives but a small percentage of his value in terms of material payment, no matter what fortune he makes, no matter what millions he earns. But the man who works as a janitor in the factory producing that invention, receives an enormous payment in proportion to the mental effort that his job requires of him. And the same is true of all men between, on all levels of ambition and ability. The man at the top of the intellectual pyramid contributes the most to all those below him, but gets nothing except his material payment, receiving no intellectual bonus from others to add to the value of his time. The man at the bottom who, left to himself, would starve in his hopeless ineptitude, contributes nothing to those above him, but receives the bonus of all of their brains. Such is the nature of the ‘competition’ between the strong and the weak of the intellect. Such is the pattern of ‘exploitation’ for which you have damned the strong.” (Ayn Rand, Atlas Shrugged.)

Marxist Determinism

Marx views the proletariat as the “exploited” and the bourgeoisie as the “exploiters”. The proletarians are perpetually the victims of the bourgeoisie, with no autonomy or free will whatsoever:

“No sooner is the exploitation of the labourer by the manufacturer, so far, at an end, that he receives his wages in cash, than he is set upon by the other portions of the bourgeoisie, the landlord, the shopkeeper, the pawnbroker, etc.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

Note how Marx regards the proletarians as somehow lacking in agency. They are unable to resist paying for too large of an apartment or house by the landlord, unable to resist buying things from the shopkeeper, and also unable to continually seek high-interest loans from the pawnbroker. (Where the “proletarian” gets the stuff to pawn, Marx doesn’t say. The proletarian envisioned by him is both simultaneously unable to afford anything but the basics in life, and also has items of value to take to the pawnshop. I suppose I’m just not steeped in enough “Marxist Dialectic” to see past the contradiction.)

Since “proletariat” is a poorly defined term, in modern times, any group that is less culturally advanced tends to be viewed by political leftists as “exploited” by whatever group they regard as “bourgeoisie” -which, in practice, ends up meaning the more intelligent, knowledgeable, and better cultured people.

Marx views people as primarily products of their environment. Their ideas, attitudes and beliefs are shaped by their “material circumstances”:

“Does it require deep intuition to comprehend that man’s ideas, views, and conception, in one word, man’s consciousness, changes with every change in the conditions of his material existence, in his social relations and in his social life?” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

Is there any sense in which Ayn Rand would agree with that? Rand recognized that a dogmatic refusal to question any aspect of the established social order seems to be a feature of many people’s minds. Rand described several different types of “collectivist thinking” that were common in human society. Two of these are the “tribal mindset” and the “second-hander”:

“What are the nature and the causes of modern tribalism? Philosophically, tribalism is the product of irrationalism and collectivism. It is a logical consequence of modern philosophy. If men accept the notion that reason is not valid, what is to guide them and how are they to live?

Obviously, they will seek to join some group—any group—which claims the ability to lead them and to provide some sort of knowledge acquired by some sort of unspecified means. If men accept the notion that the individual is helpless, intellectually and morally, that he has no mind and no rights, that he is nothing, but the group is all, and his only moral significance lies in selfless service to the group—they will be pulled obediently to join a group. But which group? Well, if you believe that you have no mind and no moral value, you cannot have the confidence to make choices—so the only thing for you to do is to join an unchosen group, the group into which you were born, the group to which you were predestined to belong by the sovereign, omnipotent, omniscient power of your body chemistry.

This, of course, is racism. But if your group is small enough, it will not be called “racism”: it will be called ‘ethnicity.’” (The Voice of Reason, “Global Balkanization”, Ayn Rand; http://aynrandlexicon.com/lexicon/tribalism.html )

“Men were taught to regard second-handers—tyrants, emperors, dictators—as exponents of egoism. By this fraud they were made to destroy the ego, themselves and others. The purpose of the fraud was to destroy the creators. Or to harness them. Which is a synonym.

From the beginning of history, the two antagonists have stood face to face: the creator and the second-hander. When the first creator invented the wheel, the first second-hander responded.

He invented altruism.

The creator—denied, opposed, persecuted, exploited—went on, moved forward and carried all humanity along on his energy. The second-hander contributed nothing to the process except the impediments. The contest has another name: the individual against the collective.” (The Fountainhead, Ayn Rand; http://aynrandlexicon.com/lexicon/second-handers.html)

For Rand, these aren’t mindsets to be blindly accepted by those who choose to think. Such irrationality should be criticized.  Social institutions, educational institutions, laws, and ethics should be aimed at critiquing and discouraging such a passive mindset. Until the early Twentieth Century, the United States of America had a set of institutions in place to discourage tribalism:

“Tribalism had no place in the United States—until recent decades. It could not take root here, its imported seedlings were withering away and turning to slag in the melting pot whose fire was fed by two inexhaustible sources of energy: individual rights and objective law; these two were the only protection man needed.” (Philosophy: Who Needs It, “The Missing Link” Ayn Rand, http://aynrandlexicon.com/lexicon/tribalism.html)

Furthermore, for Rand, tribalism and second-handedness are not an inevitable mindset. People become this way through their own default. They fail to think, and that is the result. The solution is to encourage thought. What system of social organization encourages thought and discourages the failure to think?

“Capitalism demands the best of every man—his rationality—and rewards him accordingly. It leaves every man free to choose the work he likes, to specialize in it, to trade his product for the products of others, and to go as far on the road of achievement as his ability and ambition will carry him. His success depends on the objective value of his work and on the rationality of those who recognize that value. When men are free to trade, with reason and reality as their only arbiter, when no man may use physical force to extort the consent of another, it is the best product and the best judgment that win in every field of human endeavor, and raise the standard of living—and of thought—ever higher for all those who take part in mankind’s productive activity.” (Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal, “What is Capitalism”, Ayn Rand, http://aynrandlexicon.com/lexicon/capitalism.html )

The Communist Manifesto on Women

In a departure from the more modern, “feminist”, interpretation of Marxism, The Communist Manifesto regards the damage to the family as another harm caused by the “bourgeoisie”. Specifically, Marx and Engels say capitalism has made women too independent:

“Modern Industry has converted the little workshop of the patriarchal master into the great factory of the industrial capitalist. …The less the skill and exertion of strength implied in manual labour, in other words, the more modern industry becomes developed, the more is the labour of men superseded by that of women. Differences of age and sex have no longer any distinctive social validity for the working class. All are instruments of labour, more or less expensive to use, according to their age and sex.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

For Marx, the Industrial Revolution has made it possible for women to do the work that used to be done by men, and that is a bad thing. Jobs that would have required great physical strength are replaced by machines, which can be operated by comparatively physically weaker women. Even poor women no longer need be dependent on men for their subsistence.

Further, in a knowledge-based, intelligence-based, industrial economy, intelligence becomes more important than physical strength, allowing for women to rise in the business world, if they so choose. Ayn Rand recognized this fact, which is why she created the character of Dagny Taggart in Atlas Shrugged: A female businesswoman and engineer. Rand agrees with Marx that capitalism and the Industrial Revolution gave women greater independence. As one writer in a collection of essays approved by Rand noted:

“The factories were held responsible, by such critics, for every social problem of that age, including promiscuity, infidelity, and prostitution. Implicit in the condemnation of women working in the factories was the notion that a woman’s place is in the home and that her only proper role is to keep house for her husband and to rear his children….

The factories were blamed simultaneously for removing girls from the watchful restraints of their parents and for encouraging early marriages; and later, for fostering maternal negligence and incompetent housekeeping, as well as for encouraging lack of female subordination and the desire for luxuries….” (Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal, “The Effects of the Industrial Revolution on Women and Children”, Robert Hessen.)

In reality, the factory system provided women with a means of survival and independence unavailable to them before the advent of the Industrial Revolution:

“What the factory system offered these women was—not misery and degradation—but a means of survival, of economic independence, of rising above the barest subsistence….

…women increasingly preferred work in the factories to any other alternatives open to them, such as domestic service, or back-breaking work in agricultural gangs, or working as haulers and pullers in the mines; moreover, if a woman could support herself, she was not driven into early marriage.” (Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal, “The Effects of the Industrial Revolution on Women and Children”, Robert Hessen.)

Capitalism has done more to liberate women than all the political agitation of feminists, to Marx and Engels’ consternation.

The Communist Manifesto on Property

Marx says that the abolition of property is not a “distinctive feature of communism”:

“The abolition of existing property relations is not at all a distinctive feature of communism.

All property relations in the past have continually been subject to historical change consequent upon the change in historical conditions.

The French Revolution, for example, abolished feudal property in favour of bourgeois property.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

Instead, Communism aims at the abolition of only “bourgeoisie property”:

“The distinguishing feature of Communism is not the abolition of property generally, but the abolition of bourgeois property. But modern bourgeois private property is the final and most complete expression of the system of producing and appropriating products, that is based on class antagonisms, on the exploitation of the many by the few.“ (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

Marx says he does not mean he advocates the abolition of the property acquired by “the fruit of one’s labor”:

“We Communists have been reproached with the desire of abolishing the right of personally acquiring property as the fruit of a man’s own labour, which property is alleged to be the groundwork of all personal freedom, activity and independence.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

But, Marx says, such private property is no longer a feature of the system of “bourgeoisie property”:

“Hard won, self-acquired, self-earned property! Do you mean the property of petty artisan and of the small peasant, a form of property that preceded the bourgeois form? There is no need to abolish that; the development of industry has to a great extent already destroyed it, and is still destroying it daily.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

Marx says that modern “wage labor” does not create private property for the laborer:

“But does wage-labour create any property for the labourer? Not a bit. It creates capital, i.e., that kind of property which exploits wage-labour, and which cannot increase except upon condition of begetting a new supply of wage-labour for fresh exploitation. Property, in its present form, is based on the antagonism of capital and wage labour.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

“Capital”, by which Marx seems to mean “property” as that term is understood in modern times, is collectively produced by proletarians, and is a tool of exploitation by the capitalist:

“To be a capitalist, is to have not only a purely personal, but a social status in production. Capital is a collective product, and only by the united action of many members, nay, in the last resort, only by the united action of all members of society, can it be set in motion.

Capital is therefore not only personal; it is a social power. “ (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

So, for Marx, the “liberation” of “capital” by the proletarians is not theft, it is merely an elimination of its “class character”:

“When, therefore, capital is converted into common property, into the property of all members of society, personal property is not thereby transformed into social property. It is only the social character of the property that is changed. It loses its class character.“ (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

As has already been discussed, Rand would simply have a fundamental disagreement with Marx about (a) studying groups of people and social systems without understanding the fundamental nature of man; (b) the grouping together in Marx’s mind of all people into either “proletarians” or “bourgeoisie”, without recognizing the individual nature of human beings; and (c) the assumption that technology, created by the more knowledgeable and intelligent people, is somehow “exploiting” the less knowledgeable and intelligent. Instead, Rand, in accordance with the “Pyramid of Ability” principle, would say that the more able make life better for the less able -although Rand would also adamantly say this is not, and should not be, the life’s goal of property owners:

“The Objectivist ethics proudly advocates and upholds rational selfishness—which means: the values required for man’s survival qua man…” (The Virtue of Selfishness, “The Objectivist Ethics”, Ayn Rand; http://aynrandlexicon.com/lexicon/selfishness.html)

For Marx, property rights are a form of “exploitation”. For Rand, property rights are moral principles defining and sanctioning an individual’s freedom of action to live his life in a social environment. To create the material means of his survival and flourishing:

“Bear in mind that the right to property is a right to action, like all the others: it is not the right to an object, but to the action and the consequences of producing or earning that object. It is not a guarantee that a man will earn any property, but only a guarantee that he will own it if he earns it. It is the right to gain, to keep, to use and to dispose of material values.” (The Virtue of Selfishness, “Man’s Rights”, Ayn Rand.)

Also, for Rand, since the interests of rational men generally do not conflict in a free society, the fact that the more able are able to produce great new technologies actually benefits their intellectual inferiors, in accordance with the economic principle of “comparative advantage” and Rand’s concept of the “pyramid of ability”.

Marxist Epistemology

For Marx, at least when it comes to normative concepts like “law”, “morality” and “government”, there is no such thing as “objectivity” -of “true” and “false”.  All ideas are just a product of one’s “material conditions”:

“But don’t wrangle with us so long as you apply, to our intended abolition of bourgeois property, the standard of your bourgeois notions of freedom, culture, law, &c. Your very ideas are but the outgrowth of the conditions of your bourgeois production and bourgeois property, just as your jurisprudence is but the will of your class made into a law for all, a will whose essential character and direction are determined by the economical conditions of existence of your class.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto; emphasis added.)

Marx views the contents of the human mind, our ideas, as nothing but a sort of rationalization for advancing our class. For instance, when addressing some of the criticisms of communism, Marx notes that:

“The charges against Communism made from a religious, a philosophical and, generally, from an ideological standpoint, are not deserving of serious examination.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

Why does Marx dismiss philosophical and “ideological” criticisms of his viewpoint? Because all philosophy and ideology is nothing but rationalization for him. There is no such thing as “objectivity” for Marx and Engels:

“Does it require deep intuition to comprehend that man’s ideas, views, and conception, in one word, man’s consciousness, changes with every change in the conditions of his material existence, in his social relations and in his social life?” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

The predominate ideas of a society are nothing but the “ideas of the ruling class”:

“What else does the history of ideas prove, than that intellectual production changes its character in proportion as material production is changed? The ruling ideas of each age have ever been the ideas of its ruling class.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

Education of children is premised on the idea that some ideas are true, while others are false. It is also based in the belief that some concepts will help you to live your life better. You learn how to read because literacy is better than being illiterate. It allows for greater communication and easier learning. You learn arithmetic to keep a budget of your spending, and to determine quantities more quickly than you could through simple counting. You learn calculus to be able to determine the instantaneous velocity of a rocket to put satellites into orbit for tracking the weather. Etc., etc. But for Marx, all education is nothing but a perpetuation of the system of exploitation by the “bourgeoisie”:

“And your education! Is not that also social, and determined by the social conditions under which you educate, by the intervention direct or indirect, of society, by means of schools, &c.? The Communists have not invented the intervention of society in education; they do but seek to alter the character of that intervention, and to rescue education from the influence of the ruling class.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto; emphasis added.)

Normative concepts like “law” or “morality” for Marx merely reflect the “selfish interests” of some particular group. All such concepts are merely a reflection of “present modes of production”:

The selfish misconception that induces you to transform into eternal laws of nature and of reason, the social forms springing from your present mode of production and form of property – historical relations that rise and disappear in the progress of production – this misconception you share with every ruling class that has preceded you. What you see clearly in the case of ancient property, what you admit in the case of feudal property, you are of course forbidden to admit in the case of your own bourgeois form of property.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto; emphasis added.)

Strangely, Marx uses the term “selfishness” here to refer to a group interest, not self-interest -the supposed group interest of the “bourgeoisie”, whatever that is.

Rand agrees with Marx that reason and the discovery of laws of nature is only necessary if one is selfish. She agrees that property rights are related to selfishness. But, for Rand, “selfishness” is actually related to a “self”, which Marx, as a collectivist, barely even recognizes:

“…the exact meaning and dictionary definition of the word “selfishness” is: concern with one’s own interests.

This concept does not include a moral evaluation; it does not tell us whether concern with one’s own interests is good or evil; nor does it tell us what constitutes man’s actual interests. It is the task of ethics to answer such questions.”  (The Virtue of Selfishness, “The Objectivist Ethics”, Ayn Rand.)

Rand, unlike Marx, regards one’s self-interest as the only reason ethics, politics, or any other normative concept is necessary. It is because one chooses to live that ethics, rights, or questions of the concept of “property” even arise:

“There is only one fundamental alternative in the universe: existence or non-existence—and it pertains to a single class of entities: to living organisms….It is only the concept of “Life” that makes the concept of “Value” possible. It is only to a living entity that things can be good or evil.” (Atlas Shrugged, Ayn Rand, emphasis added.)

Marx, like almost every philosopher before him, starts from the assumption that the only way for there to be “truly objective” concepts like “rights”, “law”, “government” or “ethics” is to somehow eliminate all self-interest from the equation. Since that is not possible without dying, Marx throws up his hands and declares the whole enterprise to find objective law and government nothing but  “….the outgrowth of the conditions of your bourgeois production and bourgeois property…”

Rand, on the other hand, recognizes that it is only because one wants to live that these concepts are necessary. Therefore, an objective definition of “rights” or “law”, to say nothing of morality, depends on man’s choice to live:

“My morality, the morality of reason, is contained in a single axiom: existence exists—and in a single choice: to live. The rest proceeds from these.” (Atlas Shrugged, Ayn Rand)

The Communist Manifesto’s Nihilistic Tendency

As discussed, Marx views all ideas as nothing but the ideas of the “ruling class”:

“What else does the history of ideas prove, than that intellectual production changes its character in proportion as material production is changed? The ruling ideas of each age have ever been the ideas of its ruling class. “ (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

In reality, some ideas are true and others are false. What makes an idea “true” or false”? It’s correspondence to reality. The idea that the Earth is flat is false and the idea that the Earth is round is true. Why does one accept the latter and reject the former? Because it has consequences for living. If you operated on the assumption that the Earth was flat, it would lead to a whole host of contradictions, and would put you at war with reality. Human life would be worse if people continued to insist that the Earth was flat.

People who continue to accept false ideas will be less successful at living. People who insist that vaccination is, on the whole, bad for them, will tend to be killed by that idea. People who regard vaccination as generally a good will tend to live longer and better lives.

Taken to its logical extreme, a Marxist analysis of vaccination will call it nothing but a “bourgeoisie prejudice” and claim that the reason the vaccinated live longer and better lives than the unvaccinated is due to “exploitation” of the later by the former.

Furthermore, taken to its logical extreme, a Marxist analysis of vaccination would say that precisely because people who are vaccinated are living longer is proof that they are exploiters, and that they must be “swept aside”. The desire to live as the basis for objectivity is regarded as a distorting agent by Marxists. Those implementing Marxist political theory will then hold a simmering grudge against the successful and the able. The able tend to be the people who want to live, and therefore conform the contents of their minds to reality in order to achieve that objective. Marxist resentment will focus on the most rational and most successful people. It focuses it’s hatred on us, the living. The Marxist mindset is a psychology of nihilism -of hatred of the good.

This is why Marxism tends to devolve into full-throttle mass-murder and destruction of the able wherever it is implemented. (For instance, Pol Pot and the Khmer Rouge murdered anyone who spoke a foreign language or wore glasses because they were viewed as intellectuals -as people who used ideas to improve their lives.  https://www.bbc.com/news/world-asia-pacific-10684399)

Marx said:

“The Communist revolution is the most radical rupture with traditional property relations; no wonder that its development involved the most radical rupture with traditional ideas.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

“The Communists disdain to conceal their views and aims. They openly declare that their ends can be attained only by the forcible overthrow of all existing social conditions.” (Communist Manifesto; https://oll.libertyfund.org/page/marx-manifesto)

In practice, this has meant the Killing Fields of Cambodia, the Cultural Revolution of China, and the Gulags of Stalinist Russia. The blood of the people murdered under those regimes is on the intellectual hands of Marx and Engels.

The Ideas of William James Compared and Contrasted With Those of Ayn Rand

William James’ attempt to defend religious faith leads him to several conclusions regarding morality and reason that are contrary to Ayn Rand’s life-centered view of morality. This, in turn, causes James to attempt to confine the methods of observation and logic to science, while saying it is inapplicable in the realm of morality. James makes this distinction between science and morality by saying both are ultimately expressions of nothing but “will”. James’ view has consequences in the areas of human social relations and politics.

This paper will compare and contrast Rand’s philosophy with that of James by looking at some of his essays from his book, The Will to Believe And Other Essays in Popular Philosophy, Copyright 1896) (https://www.gutenberg.org/files/26659/26659-h/26659-h.htm.)

For Starters: William James Wants to Defend Religion

I was surprised when I discovered that much of William James’ work seemed aimed at defending religious belief. In the preface to his book, James says:

“The first four essays are largely concerned with defending the legitimacy of religious faith.” (Preface)

“…academic audiences, fed already on science, have a very different need. Paralysis of their native capacity for faith and timorous abulia in the religious field are their special forms of mental weakness, brought about by the notion, carefully instilled, that there is something called scientific evidence by waiting upon which they shall escape all danger of shipwreck in regard to truth. But there is really no scientific or other method by which men can steer safely between the opposite dangers of believing too little or of believing too much.” (Preface, emphasis added.)

“I do not think that any one can accuse me of preaching reckless faith. I have preached the right of the individual to indulge his personal faith at his personal risk. I have discussed the kinds of risk; I have contended that none of us escape all of them; and I have only pleaded that it is better to face them open-eyed than to act as if we did not know them to be there.” (Preface)

How Does William James Go About Defending Religion?
James’ defense of religious belief rests in his premise that certain things we hold to be true are based in our “passional and volitional nature”:

“The next matter to consider is the actual psychology of human opinion. When we look at certain facts, it seems as if our passional and volitional nature lay at the root of all our convictions. When we look at others, it seems as if they could do nothing when the intellect had once said its say. Let us take the latter facts up first.” (THE WILL TO BELIEVE, William James)

In other words, there are certain things, according to James, that we want to be true, and there is no further basis for the belief than that. The desire to be scientific is just a manifestation of an “inner need”:

“Hardly a law has been established in science, hardly a fact ascertained, which was not first sought after, often with sweat and blood, to gratify an inner need.” (IS LIFE WORTH LIVING?, William James, emphasis added.)

He makes no distinction between the “inner need” that some feel to be scientific, and the “inner need” that others feel to be religious. Both such “inner needs” cannot be analyzed any further:

Whence such needs come from we do not know; we find them in us, and biological psychology so far only classes them with Darwin’s ‘accidental variations.’ But the inner need of believing that this world of nature is a sign of something more spiritual and eternal than itself is just as strong and authoritative in those who feel it, as the inner need of uniform laws of causation ever can be in a professionally scientific head. The toil of many generations has proved the latter need prophetic. Why may not the former one be prophetic, too?” (IS LIFE WORTH LIVING?, William James, emphasis added.)

The fact that science is based on observed facts, and religion is not, doesn’t matter to James. What matters is the satisfaction of these ineffable “inner needs”:

And if needs of ours outrun the visible universe, why may not that be a sign that an invisible universe is there? What, in short, has authority to debar us from trusting our religious demands?” (IS LIFE WORTH LIVING?, William James, emphasis added.)

The desire to be scientific is no better or worse than the desire to believe on the basis of faith:

“Science as such assuredly has no authority, for she can only say what is, not what is not; and the agnostic ‘thou shalt not believe without coercive sensible evidence’ is simply an expression (free to any one to make) of private personal appetite for evidence of a certain peculiar kind.” (IS LIFE WORTH LIVING?, William James, emphasis added.)

What James Calls “Matters of Fact”
Does William James want to throw out all facts and science? No. He just wants to “carve out” a subset of ideas that will be immune from facts and science. To accomplish this, he starts by agreeing that there are certain “matters of fact” that no one can deny, no matter how much they want them to be otherwise:

“Does it not seem preposterous on the very face of it to talk of our opinions being modifiable at will? Can our will either help or hinder our intellect in its perceptions of truth? Can we, by just willing it, believe that Abraham Lincoln’s existence is a myth, {5} and that the portraits of him in McClure’s Magazine are all of some one else? Can we, by any effort of our will, or by any strength of wish that it were true, believe ourselves well and about when we are roaring with rheumatism in bed, or feel certain that the sum of the two one-dollar bills in our pocket must be a hundred dollars? We can say any of these things, but we are absolutely impotent to believe them; and of just such things is the whole fabric of the truths that we do believe in made up,—matters of fact, immediate or remote, as Hume said, and relations between ideas, which are either there or not there for us if we see them so, and which if not there cannot be put there by any action of our own.” (THE WILL TO BELIEVE, William James, emphasis added.)

To James, Knowledge is Conditioned By Our Acceptance Of What Others Tell Us, So It is Not Solely Based in Logic or Even Experience -Knowledge Contains An Element of “Will” or “Simple Wishing”
There are, for James, other areas of human belief where our knowledge is conditioned by an “act of will”, and not by mere observation of facts and the application of logic. James calls this “simple wishing”:

Free-will and simple wishing do seem, in the matter of our credences, to be only fifth wheels to the coach. Yet if any one should thereupon assume that intellectual insight is what remains after wish and will and sentimental preference have taken wing, or that pure reason is what then settles our opinions, he would fly quite as directly in the teeth of the facts.” (THE WILL TO BELIEVE, William James, emphasis added.)

For James, the method of logic, and the scientific method seem to be things that are just “socially accepted”, and have no further justification:

Our faith is faith in some one else’s faith, and in the greatest matters this is most the case. Our belief in truth itself, for instance, that there is a truth, and that our minds and it are made for each other,—what is it but a passionate affirmation of desire, in which our social system backs us up? We want to have a truth; we want to believe that our experiments and studies and discussions must put us in a continually better and better position towards it; and on this line we agree to fight out our thinking lives. But if a pyrrhonistic sceptic asks us how we know all this, can our logic find a reply? No! certainly it cannot. It is just one volition against another,—we willing to go in for life upon a trust or assumption which he, for his part, does not care to make.” (THE WILL TO BELIEVE, William James, emphasis added.)

James concludes that our “non-intellectual nature” influences our convictions. We have “passional tendencies and volitions” which are unavoidable in coming to conclusions:

Evidently, then, our non-intellectual nature does influence our convictions. There are passional tendencies and volitions which run before and others which come after belief, and it is only the latter that are too late for the fair; and they are not too late when the previous passional work has been already in their own direction.” (THE WILL TO BELIEVE, William James, emphasis added.)

In a certain context, I think this is true. Many of our needs as living organisms come from the time we are born, and can be said, in that sense, to be “pre-conceptual”. A young child starts out as a perceptual being, similar to an animal, that learns to use his mind to promote his life. You could call that “our non-intellectual nature”, but, William James isn’t talking about this. In the previous quote, he is talking about our convictions based in the authority of what others have told us.

In reality, we don’t look for food because our parents told us to. We look for food because even the most simple-minded person, with a functioning brain, recognizes it is necessary -if one desires to live. (Although that desire may be implicit rather than explicit.) Feeling that you are hungry, “simply wishing” to satiate it, and using your reason to satisfy that “simple wish” by hunting for food, or growing food, by following observed cause and effect relationships, is one thing. It is not the same as having a “simple wish” that what your elders tell you, or your preacher tells you, is right without your own investigation of the facts. The feeling of hunger is based in observed facts regarding your body’s need for food. The feeling of the existence of an afterlife is not based on any such observed facts.

Of course, I think James will say that the desire to operate in accordance with observed facts is, itself, nothing but a “feeling” with no basis in anything observed. But, if I “simply wish” to live, then adopting the method of observation of facts and the use of logic is necessary. All reason is based in the “simple wish” to live. Reason isn’t necessary for those who do not desire to live, according to Ayn Rand. But, if you “simply wish” to live, then you must reject ideas that would be contrary to that “simple wish” because reality is what it is, and your body is what it is.

To Ayn Rand, anything in the bible that runs contrary to the dictates of reality must be discarded, if you want to live. The idea of god must be held as an arbitrary assertion, without basis in observed facts, and discarded -if you want to live.

Rand’s atheism is based in the “simple wish” -by which I mean, a realistically obtainable desire- to live, combined with the observation that existence exists.

James Starts With the Cartesian “Prior-Certainty of Consciousness”
For James, on the other hand, there is no acknowledgement that existence exists. He starts from what Rand calls “the prior certainty of consciousness”:

There is but one indefectibly certain truth, and that is the truth that pyrrhonistic scepticism itself leaves standing,—the truth that the present phenomenon of consciousness exists.” (THE WILL TO BELIEVE, William James, emphasis added.)

There is no objectivity because he will not acknowledge “the primacy of existence”:

“No concrete test of what is really true has ever been agreed upon. Some make the criterion external to the moment of perception, putting it either in revelation, the consensus gentium, the instincts of the heart, or the systematized experience of the race.” (THE WILL TO BELIEVE, William James.)

Rand starts from the standpoint of looking outward, and then recognizing that consciousness is that which perceives reality:

“The primacy of existence (of reality) is the axiom that existence exists, i.e., that the universe exists independent of consciousness (of any consciousness), that things are what they are, that they possess a specific nature, an identity. The epistemological corollary is the axiom that consciousness is the faculty of perceiving that which exists—and that man gains knowledge of reality by looking outward. The rejection of these axioms represents a reversal: the primacy of consciousness—the notion that the universe has no independent existence, that it is the product of a consciousness (either human or divine or both). The epistemological corollary is the notion that man gains knowledge of reality by looking inward (either at his own consciousness or at the revelations it receives from another, superior consciousness).” (Ayn Rand, Philosophy: Who Needs It, “The Metaphysical Versus The Man-Made”)

Now it is apparent why William James regards the “need” to be scientific and the “need” to be religious as two unanalyzable facts. All that is truly real for him is consciousness. Our senses cannot be trusted, and therefore we cannot be certain there is any reality. There can be no observation of facts that, combined with our desire to live, make rationality and science necessary. His previously quoted discussion of science and religion as serving “inner needs” now makes perfect sense, given William James’ philosophic starting points:

Whence such needs come from we do not know; we find them in us, and biological psychology so far only classes them with Darwin’s ‘accidental variations.’ But the inner need of believing that this world of nature is a sign of something more spiritual and eternal than itself is just as strong and authoritative in those who feel it, as the inner need of uniform laws of causation ever can be in a professionally scientific head. The toil of many generations has proved the latter need prophetic. Why may not the former one be prophetic, too? And if needs of ours outrun the visible universe, why may not that be a sign that an invisible universe is there? What, in short, has authority to debar us from trusting our religious demands? Science as such assuredly has no authority, for she can only say what is, not what is not; and the agnostic ‘thou shalt not believe without coercive sensible evidence’ is simply an expression (free to any one to make) of private personal appetite for evidence of a certain peculiar kind.” (IS LIFE WORTH LIVING?, William James, emphasis added.)

William James Thinks “Belief In Something”, Even If Wrong, Is Better Than, What He Views, As “Constant Uncertainty”
James believes that “belief in something” is better than the “constant uncertainty” that he thinks philosophy, and a reality-oriented approach leads to:

“Believe truth! Shun error!—these, we see, are two materially different laws; and by choosing between them we may end by coloring differently our whole intellectual life.” (THE WILL TO BELIEVE, William James.)

“We may regard the chase for truth as paramount, and the avoidance of error as secondary; or we may, on the other hand, treat the avoidance of error as more imperative, and let truth take its chance. Clifford, in the instructive passage which I have quoted, exhorts us to the latter course. Believe nothing, he tells us, keep your mind in suspense forever, rather than by closing it on insufficient evidence incur the awful risk of believing lies.” (THE WILL TO BELIEVE, William James.)

If you still doubt him, James reminds you that our desire for truth over error is nothing but an “expression of passional life”, so it is no better or worse than the “passion” of those who choose to believe the bible, despite evidence to the contrary:

“I myself find it impossible to go with Clifford. We must remember that these feelings of our duty about either truth or error are in any case only expressions of our passional life. Biologically considered, our minds are as ready to grind out falsehood as veracity…” (THE WILL TO BELIEVE, William James, emphasis added.)

The above quote draws out a sharp distinction between Ayn Rand and William James. He sees no connection between truth and the choice to live. (Which, for Rand, is a choice, not a commandment.) He views the search for truth, and the avoiding of error as a “duty”, which is an expression of “our passional life”.

Rand, on the other hand, says that if you want to live, then you must recognize that reality is what it is, and operate in accordance with immutable cause and effect. Only the “man-made” is “contingent” for Ayn Rand. Nature, apart from human action, is “necessary’ and “had to be”. According to Rand, you judge the man-made, and accept the “metaphysically given”. (Ayn Rand, Philosophy: Who Needs It, “The Metaphysical Versus The Man-Made”)

Placed in a certain context of knowledge, I think Rand would believe it is true that reason does depend on our “passional life”, if by that expression, one means the desire to live. It’s only the choice to live that makes observing the facts, and drawing inferences and conclusions from them, necessary. William James doesn’t mean that, however.

When James speaks of our “passional life”, he means things we want to believe because they satisfy some emotional whim that may or may not enhance one’s life and well-being. His expressed goal is to justify belief in the supernatural. In practice, this means belief in what your mother, father, and minister told you as a child, based on nothing but their authority in your mind. Even more fundamentally, this represents a desire to continue to believe anything despite the fact that it is: (a) contrary to the facts, and (b) therefore contrary to your needs as a living being (and anti-life).

For instance, imagine you are dating an abusive romantic partner who beats you up. Your emotions tell you that you want to stay with them because of some neurotic need. (The origins of that need may depend on the particular individual, and are for mental health professionals to determine.) For James, this desire, or “expression of our passional life”, is no different than the desire to live, and the consequent need to observe facts and act according to them.
Another example: You have an extreme “passion” for doing heroin. (Once again, the origins of that desire may vary between people, and are for a medical professional/scientist to diagnose.) Your feelings tell you that you need to shoot up. Your rational mind tells you that if you keep this up, it will adversely affect your health, and will likely cause your untimely death. To William James, the “passion” to shoot up heroin is the same as the “passion” to follow the laws of logic or mathematics. This is because, at root, for him, reason has no connection to the “passion to live”.

In stark contrast Rand says:

“My morality, the morality of reason, is contained in a single axiom: existence exists—and in a single choice: to live. The rest proceeds from these.” (Ayn Rand, For The New Intellectual, Galt’s Speech. )

Ayn Rand’s “passion” is the desire to live, and this desire, combined with the immutable laws of nature, creates the need for a moral code based in reason.

William James’ Methodological Distinction in Natural Sciences versus In The Realm of Morality
James doesn’t want to throw science out entirely. So, he distinguishes between committing to a particular belief, versus remaining uncommitted, because you don’t have enough evidence, in different areas of life:

“Wherever the option between losing truth and gaining it is not momentous, we can throw the chance of gaining truth away, and at any rate save ourselves from any chance of believing falsehood, by not making up our minds at all till objective evidence has come.” (THE WILL TO BELIEVE, William James.)

“In scientific questions, this is almost always the case; and even in human affairs in general, the need of acting is seldom so urgent that a false belief to act on is better than no belief at all.” (THE WILL TO BELIEVE, William James.)

I think he is saying that in the natural sciences, we can often remain uncommitted to a particular scientific theory because there is no great rush to decide. For instance, the theory of evolution has less immediate impact on our personal lives than, say, whether someone we know has committed a serious crime. Knowing that someone is a murderer, and is to be shunned, to avoid being killed oneself, is of greater immediate concern to most people than whether Darwinian evolution or Lamarckian evolution is correct.

James distinguishes many scientific issues, like the theory of evolution, from a court case:

“Law courts, indeed, have to decide on the best evidence attainable for the moment, because a judge’s duty is to make law as well as to ascertain it, and (as a learned judge once said to me) few cases are worth spending much time over: the great thing is to have them decided on any acceptable principle, and got out of the way. But in our dealings with objective nature we obviously are recorders, not makers, of the truth; and decisions for the mere sake of deciding promptly and getting on to the next business would be wholly out of place.” (THE WILL TO BELIEVE, William James, emphasis added.)

I take James as meaning that sometimes, what is needed is a quick, and decisive opinion by the judge, not necessarily the “optimal” choice. A decision, one way or the other, is what is needed, rather than waiting to get more data.

As a legal professional, I’m not sure I 100% agree with his example here. In a death penalty case, a “prompt” decision is not better than the “optimal” decision of determining whether the defendant is actually guilty. The possibility of a mistake in a criminal case is unacceptable. In certain breach of contract disputes, he probably does have a better point. (And, this is why criminal cases require a higher burden of proof.) At any rate, it is true that sometimes you must make a quick decision because waiting is less optimal than either decision you could make. When an out of control truck is about to run you down on the street, you may not have time to decide whether jumping right or jumping left is better. You’ve got to jump, immediately, so less analysis goes into the decision than would be the case with more time. (The stakes are very high, but the time to decide creates a less than optimal analysis -but more optimal than waiting.)

James Probably makes the distinction between Morality (“oughts”) on the one hand, and scientific questions (“Is-statements”) on the other because of the “Is-Ought problem”:

“The question next arises: Are there not somewhere forced options in our speculative questions, and can we (as men who may be interested at least as much in positively gaining truth as in merely escaping dupery) always wait with impunity till the coercive evidence shall have arrived? It seems a priori improbable that the truth should be so nicely adjusted to our needs and powers as that.”

“Moral questions immediately present themselves as questions whose solution cannot wait for sensible proof. A moral question is a question not of what sensibly exists, but of what is good, or would be good if it did exist. Science can tell us what exists; but to compare the worths, both of what exists and of what does not exist, we must consult not science, but what Pascal calls our heart.” (THE WILL TO BELIEVE, William James, emphasis added.)

For James, as for David Hume, morality, that which one “ought to do”, is not something that can be derived from observing “what sensibly exists”. Morality is based in “our heart”, by which he means some feeling other than what we can see.

I do not think that Ayn Rand’s response to this would be to say that the mere observation of facts creates any kind of “moral commandment” or “duty” to live. Observation of facts will demonstrate that life is conditional, and that it is not guaranteed to us. Observation of facts will also lead to the conclusion that certain actions must be taken to maintain one’s life. Observation will also lead you to understand that a certain methodology maximizes the probability of living. However, the choice to live, for Rand, is a choice. (A “basic” choice) :

“Life or death is man’s only fundamental alternative. To live is his basic act of choice. If he chooses to live, a rational ethics will tell him what principles of action are required to implement his choice. If he does not choose to live, nature will take its course.” (Ayn Rand, Philosophy: Who Needs It, “Causality versus Duty”)

As a teenager or young adult, possibly younger, most of us have a “background knowledge” we have gained from observation, school, and our elders. Some of it is right, and some of it is not. Also, by the time we’re in our teenage years, most of us are able to have some conception of our own lives, and to recognize that living is conditional on our actions. With this “cognitive context”, we then make that choice to live, over and over, throughout our lives. To the extent that we recognize, implicitly or explicitly, that rationality is necessary for our survival, we can then reform, and adapt some of our ideas, or flatly reject, others.

I think the difference between Rand on the one hand, and William James, and David Hume, on the other, is that Rand would say something like this:

Why do you need science at all? Why do you need to reason at all?

For Rand, it is only the “basic choice” to live, combined with the axiom “existence exists”, that demands you observe facts and make logical conclusions based on those observations. From this basis, Rand develops a morality based in the virtue of rationality, aimed at pursuing the cardinal values of Reason, Purpose, and Self-esteem. These three components constitute the essence of “man’s life” for Rand.

Rand does base morality in what “sensibly exists”, which is the nature of existence, and the choice to live. Does one have to live according to Rand? No, it is a choice. But for those who choose life, there is no other option but the virtue of rationality.

The difference between Rand and William James is that he is not recognizing why we need morality at all. He wants to find some basis for holding “traditional morality”, which, for Western Man, is some variant of the Judeo-Christian system of morality. To that end, James is willing to equate the passion of the scientific search for the truth with the “passion” to believe what your parents and ministers told you as a child. In the process, he disregards the “reason that we reason”, which is the enhancement and promotion of human life. Once the choice to live is jettisoned as conditioning our quest for knowledge, the entire endeavor of science becomes, psychologically, and existentially, pointless. Religion, or any other irrationalism, is then just as meaningful. (Or equally lacking in meaning.)

Since James rejects life as the standard of value in favor of Judeo-Christian morality, he is left with nothing but skepticism with respect to all knowledge:

“If we had an infallible intellect with its objective certitudes, we might feel ourselves disloyal to such a perfect organ of knowledge in not trusting to it exclusively, in not waiting for its releasing word. But if we are empiricists, if we believe that no bell in us tolls to let us know for certain when truth is in our grasp, then it seems a piece of idle fantasticality to preach so solemnly our duty of waiting for the bell.” (THE WILL TO BELIEVE, William James, emphasis added.)

The “bell that tolls in us” when it comes to the certainty of our knowledge is the concept of man’s life:

“Man has a single basic choice: to think or not, and that is the gauge of his virtue.” (Ayn Rand, For The New Intellectual, Galt’s Speech.)

“Virtue is not an end in itself. Virtue is not its own reward or sacrificial fodder for the reward of evil. Life is the reward of virtue—and happiness is the goal and the reward of life.” (Ayn Rand, For The New Intellectual, Galt’s Speech. )

For William James, Certain Types of Facts Can Be Created By Enough People Feeling that It Is So
Social organization and the relations among men are ultimately based in a moral code. Both Rand and William James would agree on this point.

In the case of James, his moral system is ultimately based in a faith that he believes is no different than the “faith in science”:

“There are, then, cases where a fact cannot come at all unless a preliminary faith exists in its coming. And where faith in a fact can help create the fact, that would be an insane logic which should say that faith running ahead of scientific evidence is the ‘lowest kind of immorality’ into which a thinking being can fall. Yet such is the logic by which our scientific absolutists pretend to regulate our lives!” (THE WILL TO BELIEVE, William James.)

James’ morality is based in faith, or more specifically, the “will to believe” in faith. Therefore, all social systems are also based in “the will to believe” for him:

“A social organism of any sort whatever, large or small, is what it is because each member proceeds to his own duty with a trust that the other members will simultaneously do theirs. Wherever a desired result is achieved by the co-operation of many independent persons, its existence as a fact is a pure consequence of the precursive faith in one another of those immediately concerned. A government, an army, a commercial system, a ship, a college, an athletic team, all exist on this condition, without which not only is nothing achieved, but nothing is even attempted.” (THE WILL TO BELIEVE, William James.)

James’ belief that social systems are based in nothing but “the will to believe” has an interesting logical consequence in practice. When a society fails, it is based in the lack of sufficient “will”. He gives the example of the robbery of a train:

“A whole train of passengers (individually brave enough) will be looted by a few highwaymen, simply because the latter can count on one another, while each passenger fears that if he makes a movement of resistance, he will be shot before any one else backs him up. If we believed that the whole car-full would rise at once with us, we should each severally rise, and train-robbing would never even be attempted.” (THE WILL TO BELIEVE, William James.)

While James leaves the realm of science to evidence and logic, the area ultimately governing human behavior, morality, is left to “will” or “passion”. For him, any social system can “work” if enough people believe it. This is because you cannot derive “ought statements” from “is statements”, an idea he got from David Hume, and, also because of what I think is an additional part, which is in bold here:

“Moral questions immediately present themselves as questions whose solution cannot wait for sensible proof. A moral question is a question not of what sensibly exists, but of what is good, or would be good if it did exist.” (THE WILL TO BELIEVE, William James, emphasis added.)

A social system is good because enough people believe it “should exist”, or because it “should work”. In other words, because enough people feel that it is so, then it is so, according to William James.

Rand denies that any social system can “work” if enough people believe it. For her, reality is what it is. Capitalism leads to prosperity and communism leads to its opposite, no matter how many people sincerely want collectivism to “work”.

Rand says that if enough people want to live, and consistently understand that choice to live, then certain social systems are better than others in achieving that goal. For Rand, individuals must be free to pursue their own rational self-interest. If they all do so, within a system of government that protects and respects rights to private property, then such a system is practical. Free market capitalism will be the social result.

Rand denies that all it takes is enough people “believing” in socialism for it to lead to prosperity. It denies the existence of the individual, whose own life is important to him, because he chooses to live. (Those who don’t choose to live need no morality, social system, or system of government.) Since there is no “social organism”, and “society” is just a number of individuals, the ultimate result of any socialist system is the war of all against all, and the destruction of the society:

“The alleged goals of socialism were: the abolition of poverty, the achievement of general prosperity, progress, peace and human brotherhood. The results have been a terrifying failure—terrifying, that is, if one’s motive is men’s welfare.
Instead of prosperity, socialism has brought economic paralysis and/or collapse to every country that tried it. The degree of socialization has been the degree of disaster. The consequences have varied accordingly.” (Ayn Rand, The Virtue of Selfishness, “The Monument Builders”.)

The ideas of William James and other late 19th-Century American Philosophers are known as “Pragmatism”. This is premised in their supposed “practicality”. But, as we have seen, James banishes science into a sort of “intellectual ghetto” by saying the “will” to pursue science is based in nothing but the same “will” to believe what the Bible says. James makes observation and scientific knowledge ultimately purposeless. In contrast, Rand, says we must practice observation and the method of logic, no matter how strongly we “want to believe” in their contraries, because it is the only way to practice the art of living.